Donate books to help fund our work. Learn more→

The Rudolf Steiner Archive

a project of Steiner Online Library, a public charity

The Riddle of Man
GA 20

A Forgotten Stream in German Spiritual Life

[ 1 ] Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel appear in their full significance quite especially to someone who considers the far-reaching impetus they gave to personalities possessed of far less spiritual vigor than they. Something is moving and working in the souls of this trio of thinkers that could not come fully to expression within themselves. And what is working as the basic undertone in the souls of these thinkers works on in a living way in their successors and brings them to world views—in accordance with the spirit—that even the three great original thinkers themselves could not achieve because they had to exhaust their soul vigor, so to speak in making the first beginnings.

[ 2 ] Thus, in Immanuel Hermann Fichte, the son of Johann Gottlieb Fichte, there appears a thinker who tries to penetrate more deeply into the spiritual than his father, Schelling, or Hegel. Whoever dares to make such an attempt will not only hear from outside the opposition of all those who are fearful about questions of world views; if he is a careful thinker, he will clearly perceive this opposition coming also from his own soul. Is there then actually a possibility of delivering the human soul of cognitive powers that lead into regions of which the senses give no view? What can guarantee the reality of such regions; what can determine the difference between such reality and the creations of fantasy and daydreaming? Whoever does not always have the spirit of this opposition at his side, so to speak, as the true companion of his prudence will easily blunder in his spiritual-scientific attempts; whoever has this spirit will recognize in it something extremely valuable for life.

Whoever enters into the arguments of Immanuel Hermann Fichte will find that a certain spiritual demeanor has passed over to him from his great predecessors that both strengthens his steps into the spiritual region and endows him with prudence in the sense just indicated.

[ 3 ] The standpoint of the Hegelian world view, which takes as its basic conviction the spiritual nature of the world of ideas, was also able to be the point of departure for Immanuel Hermann Fichte in the development of his thoughts. Nevertheless, he felt it to be a weakness in Hegel's world view that, from its supersensible vantage point, it still looks only at what is revealed in the sense world. Whoever lives into Immanuel Hermann Fichte's views can feel something like the following as its basic undertone. The soul experiences itself in a supersensible way when it lifts itself above sense perception to a weaving in the realm of ideas. Through this, the soul has not only enabled itself to see the sense world differently than the senses see it—which would correspond to the Hegelian world view—; but also, the soul has an experience of itself through this that it cannot have through anything to be found within the sense world. From now on the soul knows of something that itself is supersensible about the soul. This “something” cannot be merely the idea of the soul's sense-perceptible body. Rather, this something must be a living, essential beingness that underlies the sense-perceptible body in such a way that this body is formed according to the idea of this something. Thus Immanuel Hermann Fichte is led up above and beyond the sense-perceptible body to a supersensible body, which, out of its life, forms the first body. Hegel advances from sense observation to thinking about sense observation. Fichte seeks in man the being that can experience thinking as something supersensible, Hegel, if he wants to see in thinking something supersensible, would have to ascribe to this thinking itself the ability to think. Fichte cannot go along with this. He has to say to himself: If one is not to regard the sense-perceptible body itself as the creator of thoughts, then one is compelled to assume that there is something supersensible above and beyond this body. Moved by this kind of a view, Fichte regards the human sense-perceptible body in a natural-scientific way (physiologically), and finds that such a study, if only it is unbiased enough, is compelled to take a supersensible body as the basis of the sense-perceptible one. In paragraphs 118 and 119 of his Anthropology (second edition 1860), he says about this: “Within the material elements, therefore, one cannot find what is truly enduring, that unifying form principle of the body which proves to be operative our whole life long.” “Thus we are directed toward a second, essentially different cause within the body.” “Insofar as this [unifying form principle] contains what is actually enduring in metabolism, it is the true, inner body-invisible, yet present in all visible materiality. That other entity, the outer manifestation of this form principle, shaped by continuous metabolism: let us call it ‘corporality’ from now on; it is truly not enduring and not whole; it is the mere effect or copy of that inner bodily nature that throws it into the changing world of matter in somewhat the same way a magnetic force puts together, out of metal filing dust, a seemingly dense body that is then blown away in all directions when the uniting force is withdrawn.” This opens for Fichte the perspective of getting outside the sense world, in which man works between birth and death, into a supersensible world with which he is connected through Ws invisible body in the same way he is connected with the sense world through his visible body, For, his knowledge of this invisible body brings him to the view he expresses in these words: “For one hardly need ask here how the human being, in and for himself, conducts himself in this process of death. Man, in and for himself—even after the last, to us invisible, act of his life processes—remains, in his essential being, completely the same one he was before with respect to his spirit and power of organization. His integrity is preserved; for he has lost absolutely nothing of what was his and belonged to his substance during his visible life, He only returns in death into the invisible world; or rather, since he has never left the invisible world, since the invisible world is what actually endures within everything visible, he has only stripped off a particular form of visibility. ‘To be dead’ simply means to remain no longer perceptible to ordinary sense apprehension, in exactly the same way that what is actually real, the ultimate foundations of bodily phenomena, are also imperceptible to the senses.” And with such a thought Fichte feels himself to be standing so surely in the supersensible world that he can say: “With this concept of the continued existence of the soul, therefore, we not only transcend outer experience and reach into an unknown region of merely illusory existences; we also find ourselves, with this concept, right in the midst of the graspable reality accessible to thinking. To assert the opposite, that the soul ceases to exist, would be against nature, would contradict all analogy to outer experience. The soul that has ‘died,’ i.e., has become invisible to the senses, continues to exist no less than before, and is unremoved from its original life conditions. ... Another means of incarnation need only present itself to the soul's power of organization for the soul to stand there again in new bodily activity ...” (Paragraphs 133 Anthropology)

[ 4 ] Starting from such views there opens up for Immanuel Hermann Fichte the possibility of a self-knowledge that man attains when he observes himself from the point of view he gains through his experiences in his own supersensible entity. Man's sense-perceptible entity brings him to the point of thinking. But in thinking, after all, he grasps himself as a supersensible being, If he lifts mere thinking up into an inner experiencing—through which it is no longer mere thinking but rather a supersensible beholding,—he then gains a way of knowing through which he no longer looks only upon what is sense-perceptible, but also upon what is supersensible. If anthropology is the science of the human being by which he studies the part of himself to be found in the sense world, then, through his view of the supersensible, another science makes it appearance, about which Immanuel Hermann Fichte expresses himself in this way (paragraph 270): to “... anthropology ends up with the conclusion, established from the most varied sides, that man, in accordance with the true nature of his being, as though in the actual source of his consciousness, belongs to a supersensible world. Man's sense consciousness, on the other hand, and the phenomenal world (world of appearances) arising at the point of his eye, along with the whole life of the senses, including human senses: all this has no significance other than merely being the place in which that supersensible life of the human spirit occurs through the fact that the human spirit, by its own, free, conscious activity, leads the spiritual content of ideas from the beyond into the sense world ...” This fundamental apprehension of man's being now lifts “anthropology” in its final conclusions up to “anthroposophy.”


[ 5 ] Through Immanuel Hermann Fichte the cognitive impulse manifesting in the idealism of German world views is brought to the point of undertaking the first of those steps which can lead human insight to a science of the spiritual world. Many other thinkers strove like Immanuel Hermann Fichte to carry further the ideas of their predecessors: Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. For, this German idealism points to the germinal power for a real development of those cognitive powers of man that behold the supersensible spiritual the way our senses behold the sense-perceptible material. Let us just look at several of these thinkers. One can see how fruitful the spiritual stream of German idealism proves to be in this direction if one does not refer merely to those thinkers who are discussed in the usual textbooks on the history of philosophy, but also to those whose spiritual work was enclosed within narrower boundaries. For example, there are the Little Writings (published 1869 in Leipzig) of Johann Heinrich Deinhardt, who died in Bromberg on August 16, 1867 as headmaster of a secondary school. His book contains essays on “the antithesis between pantheism and deism in pre-Christian religions,” on the “concept of religion,” on “Kepler, his life and character,” etc. The basic undertone of these treatises is altogether of a sort to show how the thought-life of their author is rooted in the idealism of German world views. One of these essays speaks about the “reasonable grounds for believing in the immortality of the human soul.” This essay defends immortality at first only with reasons that spring from our ordinary thinking. But at the end, the following significant note is added by the publisher: “According to a letter of August 14, 1866 to his publishers, the author intended to expand this essay for the complete edition of his collected ‘Little Writings’ with an observation about the new body that the soul is working to develop for itself already in this life. The author's death the following year prevented the carrying out of this plan.” How a remark like this spotlights the effect upon thinkers of the idealism of German world views, stimulating them to penetrate in a scientific way into the spiritual realm! How many such attempts a person would discover today, even by investigating only those thinkers still to be found in literature! How many there must be that bore no fruit in literature but a great deal in life! One is looking there really, in the scientific consciousness ruling in our day, at a more or less forgotten stream in German spiritual life.

[ 6 ] One of those thinkers, hardly ever heard of today, is Ignaz Paul Vitalis Troxler. Let us mention only one of his numerous books, Lectures on Philosophy, published in 1835. A personality is expressing himself in this book who is absolutely conscious of how a person using merely his senses and the intellect that deals with the observations of his senses can know only a part of the world. Like Immanuel Hermann Fichte, Troxler also feels himself in his thinking to be standing within a supersensible world. But he also senses how the human being, when he removes himself from the power that binds him to the senses, can do more than place himself before a world that in the Hegelian sense is thought by him; through this removal he can experience within his inner being the blossoming of a purely spiritual means of knowledge through which he spiritually beholds a spiritual world, like the senses behold the sense world in sense perception. Troxler speaks of a “supra-spiritual sense:” And one can form a picture of what he means by this in the following way. The human being observes the things of the world through his senses. He thereby receives sense-perceptible pictures of these things. He then thinks about these pictures. Thoughts reveal themselves to him thereby that no longer bear the sensible pictorial element in themselves. Through the power of his spirit, therefore, man adds supersensible thoughts to the sense-perceptible pictures. If he now experiences himself in the entity that is thinking in him, in such a way that he ascends above mere thinking to spiritual experiencing, then, from out of this experiencing, an inner, purely spiritual power of picture making takes hold of him. He then beholds a world in pictures that can serve as a form of revelation for a supersensibly experienced reality. These pictures are not received by the senses; but they are full of life, just as sense-perceptible pictures are; they are not dreamed up; they are experiences in the supersensible world held fast by the soul in picture form. In ordinary cognitive activity, the sense-perceptible picture is present first and then, in the process of knowledge, the thought comes to join it—the thought, which is not a picture for the senses. In the spiritual process of knowledge, the supersensible experience is present; this experience as such could not be beheld if it did not, through a power in accordance with the nature of the spirit, pour itself into the picture that brings this power to spiritually perceptible embodiment. For Troxler, the cognitive activity of the “supra-spiritual sense” is of just such a kind. And the pictures of this supra-spiritual sense are grasped by the “supersensible spirit” of man in the same way that sense-perceptible pictures are grasped by human reason in knowledge of the sense world. In the working together of the supersensible spirit with the supra-spiritual sense, there evolved, in Troxler's view, our knowing of the spirit (see the sixth of his Lectures on Philosophy).

Taking his start from such presuppositions, Troxler has an inkling of a “higher man” within the man that experiences himself in the sense world; this “higher man” underlies the sense-perceptible man and belongs to the supersensible world; and in this view Troxler feels himself to be in harmony with what Friedrich Schlegel expressed. And thus, as was already the case earlier with Friedrich Schlegel, the highest qualities and activities manifested by the human being in the sense world become for Troxler the expression of what the supersensible human being can do. Through the fact that man stands within the sense world, his soul is possessed of the power of belief. But this power after all is only the manifestation, through the sense-perceptible body, of the supersensible soul. In the supersensible realm a certain faculty of the soul underlies our power of belief; if one wants to express it in a supersensibly pictorial way, one must call this a faculty of the supersensible man to hear. And it is the same with our power of hope. A faculty of the supersensible man to see underlies this power; corresponding with our activity of love, there is the faculty of the “higher man” to feel, to “touch,” in spirit, just as the sense of touch in the sense-perceptible world is the faculty to feel something. Troxler expresses himself on this subject (page 107 of his Lectures on Philosophy, Bern, 1835) in the following way: “Our departed friend Friedrich Schlegel has brought to light in a very beautiful and true way the relationship of the sense-perceptible to the spiritual man. In his lectures on the philosophy of language and the word, Schlegel says: ‘If one wants—in that alphabet of consciousness which provides the individual elements for the individual syllables and whole words—to refind the first beginnings of our higher consciousness, after God Himself constitutes the keystone of highest consciousness, then the feeling for the spirit must be accepted as the living center of our whole consciousness and as the point of union with the higher consciousness ... One is often used to calling these fundamental feelings for the eternal: ‘belief, hope, and love.’ If one is to regard these three fundamental feelings or characteristics or states of consciousness as just so many organs of knowledge and perception of the divine—or, if you will, at least organs that give inklings of the divine,—then one can very well compare them to the outer senses and instruments of sense perception, both in the above respect and in the characteristic form of apprehension that each of them has, Then love corresponds in a striking way—in the first stimulating soul touch, in the continuous attraction, and in the final perfect union—to the outer sense of touch; belief is the inner hearing of the spirit, uniting the given word to its higher message, grasping it, and inwardly preserving it; and hope is the eye, whose light can glimpse already in the distance the objects it craves deeply and longingly.’” That Troxler himself now goes above and beyond the meaning Schlegel gave these words and thinks them absolutely in the sense indicated above is shown by the words Troxler now adds: “Far loftier than intellect and will, and their interaction, far loftier than reason and spiritual activity (Freiheit), and their unity, are these ideas of our deeper heart (Gerrütsideen) that unite in a consciousness of spirit and of heart; and just as intellect and will, reason and spiritual activity—and all the soul capacities and abilities of a lower sort than they—represent an earthward directed reflection, so these three are a heavenward directed consciousness that is illuminated by a truly divine light.” The same thing is shown by the fact that Troxler also expresses himself about the supersensible soul body in exactly the same way one encounters in Immanuel Hermann Fichte: “Earlier philosophers have already distinguished a fine and noble soul body from the coarser body ... a soul that had about itself a picture of the body that they called a schema and that was for them the inner, higher man. ... In modern times even Kant, in The Dreams of a Spirit Seer, dreams up seriously as a joke a completely inward soul man that bears all the members of its outer man upon his spiritual body; Lavater also writes and thinks in this way; and even when Jean Paul jokes about Bonet's slip and Platner's soul girdle, which are supposed to be hidden inside the coarser outside skirt and martyr's smock, we also hear him asking again, after all: ‘to what end and from where were these extraordinary potentials and wishes laid in us, which, bare as swallowed diamonds, slowly cut our earthly covering to pieces? ... Within the stony members (of man) there grow and mature his living members according to a way of living unknown to us.’ We could,” Troxler continues, “present innumerable further examples of similar ways of thinking and writing that ultimately are only various views and pictures in which ... the one true teaching is contained of the individuality and immortality of man.”

[ 7 ] Troxler too speaks of the fact that upon the path of knowledge sought by him a science of man is possible through which—to use his own expressions—the “supra-spiritual sense” together with the “supersensible spirit” apprehend the supersensible being of man in an “anthroposophy,” On page 101 of his Lectures there is the sentence: “While it is now highly encouraging that modern philosophy, which ... must reveal itself ... in any anthroposophy, is winding its way upward, still one must not overlook the fact that this idea cannot be the fruit of speculation, and that the true individuality of man must not be confused either with what philosophy sets up as subjective spirit or as finite ‘I,’ nor with what philosophy lets this ‘I’ be confronted by as absolute spirit or absolute personality.”

[ 8 ] There is no doubt that Troxler sought the way out of and beyond Hegel's thought-world more in dim feeling than in clear perception. One can nevertheless observe in his cognitive life how the stimulus of the idealism in the German world views of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel works in a personality who cannot make the views of this trio of thinkers into his own, but who finds his own way through the fact that he receives this stimulus.


[ 9 ] Karl Christian Planck belongs to those personalities in the evolution of German spiritual life who are forgotten now and were disregarded even during their own lifetimes. He was born in 1819 in Stuttgart and died in 1880; he was a professor in a secondary school in Ulm and later in a college in Blaubeuren. In 1877 he still hoped to be given the professorship in philosophy that became free then in Tübingen. This did not happen. In a series of writings he seeks to draw near to the world view that seems to him to express the spiritual approach of the German people. In his book Outline of a Science of Nature (1864) he states how he wants, in his own thoughts. to present the thoughts of the questing German folk soul: “The author is fully aware of the power of the deep-rooted preconceptions from past views that confront his book; nevertheless, just as the work itself has fought through to completion and into public view—in spite of all the adverse conditions confronting a work of this kind as a result of the whole situation and professional position of its author—so he is also certain that what must now fight for recognition will one day appear as the simplest and most obvious truth, and that through this, not merely its concerns but also the truly German view of things will triumph over any still unworthily external and un-German grasp of nature and spirit.—What, in unconscious profound inklings, has already been prefigured in our medieval literature will finally be fulfilled by our nation in the fullness of time. Impractical, afflicted by injury and scorn, the inwardness of the German spirit (as Wolfram von Eschenbach portrayed this inwardness in his Parzival), in the power of its ceaseless striving, finally attains the highest; this inwardness beholds the ultimate simple laws of the things of this world and of human existence itself, in their very foundations; and what literature has allegorized in a fanciful medieval way as the wonders of the grail, whose rulership its hero attains, receives, on the other hand, its purely natural fulfillment and reality in a lasting knowledge of nature and of the spirit itself.”

In the last period of his life Karl Christian Planck drew his thought-world together in a book published by the philosopher Karl Köstlin in 1881 under the title Testament of a German.

[ 10 ] One can absolutely perceive in Planck's soul a similar kind of feeling for the riddle of knowledge as that revealed in the other thinker personalities characterized in this book. This riddle in its original form becomes for Planck the point of departure for his investigations. Within the circumference of the human thought-world can the strength be found by which man can apprehend true reality, the reality that gives his existence sense and meaning within world existence? Man sees himself placed into and over against nature. He can certainly form thoughts about what rules in nature's depths as powers of true being; but where is his guarantee that his thoughts have any significance at all other than that they are creations of his own soul, without kinship to those depths? If his thoughts were like this, then it would in fact remain unknown to man what he himself is and how he is rooted in the true world. Planck was just as far as Hegel from wanting to approach the world depths through any soul force other than thinking. He could hold no other view than that genuine reality must yield itself somehow to thinking. But no matter how far one reaches out with thinking, no matter how one seeks to strengthen its inner power: one still remains always only in thinking; in all the widths and depths of thinking one does not encounter being (Sein). By virtue of its own nature, thinking seems to exclude itself from any communion with being. Nevertheless, this insight into thinking's alienation from being now becomes for Planck precisely the ray of light that falls upon the world riddle and solves it. If thinking makes absolutely no claim of bearing within itself anything at all in the way of reality, if it actually is true that thinking reveals itself to be something unreal, then precisely through this fact it proves itself to be an instrument for expressing reality. If it were itself something real, then the soul could weave only in its reality, and could not leave it again; if thinking itself is unreal, then it will not disturb the soul through any reality of its own; by thinking, man is absolutely not within any thought-reality; he is within a thought-unreality that precisely therefore does not force itself upon him with its own reality but rather expresses that reality of which it speaks. Whoever sees in thinking itself something real must, in Planck's view, give up hope of arriving at reality; since, for him, thinking must place itself between the soul and reality. If thinking itself is nothing, it can therefore also not conceal reality from our activity of knowing; then reality must be able to reveal itself in thinking.

[ 11 ] With this view Planck has, to begin with, attained only the starting point for his world view. For, in the thought-weaving immediately present in the soul during life, that thinking is by no means operative which is pure, self-renouncing, and even self-denying, There play into this ordinary thought weaving what lives in the mental picturing, feeling, willing, and wanting of the soul. Because this is so, the clouding of world views occurs. And Planck's striving is to attain a kind of world view in which everything it contains is the result of thinking, yet nothing stems from thinking itself, In everything that is made into a thought about the real world, one must look at what lives in thinking but without itself being thought by us, Planck paints his picture of the world with a thinking that gives itself up in order to allow the world to shine from it.

[ 12 ] As an example of the way Planck wants to arrive at a picture of the world through such striving, let us characterize with a few strokes how he thinks about the being of the earth.

If someone pictures the earth in the way advocated by purely physical geology, then, for Planck's world view, there is no truth in this picture. To picture the earth in this way would be the same as speaking of a tree and fixing one's gaze only upon the trunk, without its leaves, blossoms, and fruit. To the sight of our physical eyes, such a tree trunk can be called reality. But in a higher sense it is no reality. For, as a mere trunk, it cannot occur as such anywhere in our world. It can be what it is only in so far as those growth forces arise in it at the same time which unfold the leaves, blossoms, and fruits. In the reality of the trunk one must think these forces in addition and must be aware that the bare trunk gives a picture of reality deceiving to the beholder, The fact that something or other is present to the senses is not yet proof that in this form it is also a reality, The earth, pictured as the totality of what it manifests in mineral configurations and in the facts occurring within these configurations, is no reality, Whoever wants to picture something real about the earth must picture it in such a way that its mineral realm already contains within itself the plant realm, Just as the trunk configuration of the tree includes its leaves and blossoms; yes, that within the “true earth” the animal realm and man are already present along with it. But do not say that all this is obvious and that Planck, basically, is only deceiving himself in thinking that not everyone sees it this way. Planck would have to reply to this: Where is the person who sees it this way? Certainly, everyone pictures the earth as a planetary body with plants, animals, and man. But they in fact picture the mineral earth, constituted of geological layers, with plants growing out of its surface, and with animals and human beings moving around on it. But this earth as a sum, added up out of minerals, plants. animals, and human beings, does not exist at all. It is only a delusion of the senses. On the other hand there is a true earth; it is a completely supersensible configuration, an invisible being, which provides the mineral foundation from out of itself; but it is not limited to this, for it manifests itself further in the plant realm, then in the animal realm, then in the human realm. Only that person has the right eye for the mineral, plant, animal, and human realm who beholds the entirety of the earth in its supersensible nature, and who feels, for example, how the picture of the material mineral realm by itself, without the picture of the soul evolution of mankind, is a delusion. Certainly, one can picture a material mineral realm to oneself; but one is living in a world-lie and not in the world-truth if, in doing so, one does not have the feeling that with a mental picture like this, one is caught in the same madness as a person who wanted to think that a man whose head has been struck off would calmly go on with his life.

It might be said: If true knowledge necessitates what is indicated here, then such knowledge, after all, could never be achieved; for, whoever asserts that the mineral earth is no reality because it must be viewed within the entirety of the earth should say too that the entirety of the earth must be viewed in the plant system and so on. Whoever raises this objection, however, has not grasped the significance of what underlies a world view that is in accordance with the spirit. In all human activity of knowing, in fact, the issue is not merely that one think correctly, but also that one think in accordance with reality. In speaking of a painting one can certainly say that one is not thinking in accordance with reality if one looks only at one person when there are three in the painting; but this assertion, within its rightful scope, cannot be refuted by the statement: No one understands this painting who also does not know all the preceding paintings of the same artist. A thinking both correct and in accordance with reality is in fact necessary for knowing reality. To consider, on their own, a mineral as a mineral, a plant as a plant, etc., can be in accordance with reality; the mineral earth is not a real configuration, however; it is a configuration of our imagination, even when one is aware of the fact that the mineral earth is only a part of everything earthly.

That is what is significant about a personality like Planck: he attains an inner state in which he does not reflect upon but rather experiences the truth of a thought; he unfolds a special power in his own soul by which to experience when not to think a particular thought because, through its own nature, it kills itself. To grasp the existence of a reality that bears within itself its own life and its own death, this belongs to the kind of soul attitude that does not depend upon the sense world to tell it: this is or this is not.

[ 13 ] From this point of view Planck sought in thinking to grasp what lives in natural phenomena and in human existence in historical, artistic, and judicial life. In a brilliant book, he wrote on the Truth and Banality of Darwinism. He calls this work a “monument to the history of modern (1872) German science.” There are people who experience a personality like Planck as hovering in unworldly conceptual heights and lacking a sense for practical life. Practical life requires people who develop healthy judgment based on “real” life, as they call it. Now, with respect to this way of experiencing Planck, one can also hold the opinion: Many things would be different in real life if this easy-going view of life and of living life were less widespread in reality, and if on the other hand the opinion could grow somewhat that thinkers like Planck—because they acquire for themselves an attitude of soul through which they unite themselves with true reality—also have a truer judgment about the relationships of life than the people who call them “dreamers in concepts” (Begriffsschwärmer) and impractical philosophers. The opinion is also possible that those dullards who are averse to such supposed “dreaming in concepts” and who think themselves so very practical in life are losing their sense for the true relationships of life, whereas the impractical philosophers are developing it to the point that it can lead them right to their goal. One can arrive at such an opinion when one considers Planck and sees in him, combined with the acme of philosophical development of ideas, a far-sighted accurate judgment about the needs of a genuine conduct of life and about the events of outer life. Even if one holds a different view about much of what Planck has developed in the way of ideas about shaping outer life—which is also the case with the present writer,—still one can acknowledge that his views can provide, precisely in this area, a sound starting point in life for solving practical problems; even if in proceeding from there one arrives at something entirely different from one's starting point. And one should assert: People who are “dreamers in concepts” in this way and who, precisely because of this, can see what powers are at work in real life are more competent to meet the needs of this real life than many a person who believes himself to be imbued with practical skill precisely through the fact that, in his view, he has not let contact with any world of ideas “make him stupid.” (In his book, Nineteenth Century Views of the World and of Life, published in 1900, the present author has written about Karl Christian Planck's place in the evolution of modern world views. This book was published in a new edition in 1914 under the title Riddles of Philosophy.)

Someone might maintain that it is unjustified to regard Planck's thoughts as significant for the motive forces of the German people since these thoughts have not become widespread. Such an opinion misses the point when speaking about the influence of the being of a people upon the views of a thinker from that people. What is working there are the impersonal (of ten unconscious) powers of a people, living in their activities in the most varied realms of existence and shaping the ideas of a thinker like Planck. These powers were there before he appeared and will work on afterward; they live, even if they are not spoken of; they live, even if they are not recognized. And it can be the case that they work in a particularly strong way in an indigenous thinker like this, who is not spoken of, because less of what these powers contain streams into the opinions held about him than into his thoughts. A thinker like this can of ten stand there alone, and not only during his lifetime; even his thoughts can stand there alone in the opinion of posterity. But if one has apprehended the particular nature of his thoughts, then one has recognized an essential trait of the folk soul, a trait that has become a thought in him and will remain imperishably in his people, ready to reveal itself in ever new impulses. Independent of the question: What effectiveness was granted to his work? is the other question: What worked in him and will lead again and again to accomplishments in the same direction? The Testament of a German by Karl Christian Planck was republished in a second edition in 1912. It is a pity that many of those who were philosophically minded and fond of writing at that time mustered up more enthusiasm for the thoughts in Henri Bergson's world view—lightly woven and therefore more easily comprehensible to undemanding souls—than for the rigorously interrelated and far-reaching ideas of Planck. How much has indeed been written about the “new configurating” of world views by Bergson: written, particularly, by those who discover the newness of a world view so easily because they lack understanding, and of ten even knowledge, of what has already been there for a long time. Relative to the “newness” of one of Bergson's main ideas the present author has pointed in his book Riddles of Philosophy to the following significant situation. (And it should be mentioned, by the way, that this indication was written before the present war. See the foreword to the second volume of the above book.)

Bergson is led by his thoughts to a transformation of the widespread idea of the evolution of organic entities. He does not set at the beginning of this evolution the simplest organism and then think that, due to outer forces, more complicated organisms emerge from it all the way up to man; he pictures that, at the starting point of evolution, there stands a being that in some form or other already contains the impulse to become man. This being, however, can bring this impulse to realization only by first expelling from itself other impulses that also lie within it. By expelling the lower organisms, this being gains the strength to realize the higher ones. Thus man, in his actual being, is not what arose last, but rather what was at work first, before everything else. He first expels the other entities from his formative powers in order to gain by this preliminary work the strength to come forth himself into outer sense-perceptible reality. Of course many will object: But numbers of people have already thought that an inner evolutionary drive was working in the evolution of organisms. And one can refer to the long-present thought of purposefulness, or to views held by natural scientists like Nageli and others. But such objections do not pertain in a case like this one. For, with Bergson's thought it is not a matter of starting from the general idea of an inner evolutionary force, but rather from a specific mental picture of what man is in his full scope; and of seeing from this picture that this man, thought of as supersensible, has impulses within him to first set the other beings of nature into sense-perceptible reality and then also to place himself into this reality.

[ 14 ] Now this is the point. What can be read in Bergson in a scintillating lightly draped configuration of ideas had already been expressed before that by the German thinker Wilhelm Heinrich Preuss in a powerful and strongly thought-through way. Preuss is also one of those personalities belonging to the presentation here of a more or less forgotten stream in the development of German world views that are in accordance with the spirit. With a powerful sense for reality, Preuss brings together natural-scientific views and world views—in his book Spirit and Matter (1882), for example. One finds the Bergsonian thought we cited expressed by Preuss in the following way: “It should ... be time ... to present a teaching about the origins of organic species that is founded not only upon principles set up in a one-sided way by descriptive natural science, but that is also in full harmony with the rest of natural laws (which are also the laws of human thinking). This teaching should also be free of any hypothesizing and should rest only upon rigorous conclusions drawn from scientific observation in the broadest sense. This teaching should rescue the concept of species as much as Is factually possible, but at the same time should take Darwin's concept of evolution into its domain and seek to make It fruitful.—The center of this new teaching is man, the species that recurs only once on our planet: homo sapiens. Strange that older observers started with objects of nature and then erred to such an extent that they did not find the path to man, in which effort even Darwin Indeed succeeded only in a most pitiful and utterly unsatisfying way by seeking the ancestor of the lord of creation among the animals. Actually, the natural scientist would have to start with himself as a human being and then, continuing on through the whole realm of existence and of thinking return to mankind ... It was not by chance that human nature arose out of earthly nature; It was by necessity. Man is the goal of tellurian processes, and every other form arising besides him has borrowed its traits from his. Man is the first-born being of the whole cosmos. ... When the germs of his being had arisen, the remaining organic element no longer had the necessary strength to engender further human germs. What arose then was animal or plant. ...”

[ 15 ] The idea, as it lives in the philosophy of German idealism's picture of the being of man, also shines forth from the mental pictures of this little-known thinker of Elsfleth, Wilhelm Heinrich Preuss. Out of this view he knows how to make Darwinism—insofar as Darwinism looks only at the evolution occurring in the sense world—into a part of a world view that Is in accordance with the spirit and that wishes to know the being of man In Its development out of the depths of the world-all. As to how Bergson arrived at his thoughts—so glittering in his depletion, but so powerfully shining in Preuss's—let us emphasize that less here than the fact that in the writings of the little-known Preuss the most fruitful seeds can be found, able to give many a person a stronger impetus than that to be found in Bergson's glittering version of these same thoughts. To be sure, one must also meet Preuss with more ability to deepen one's thinking than was shown by those who waxed so enthusiastic about the “new life” instilled in our world view by Bergson. What is being said here about Bergson and Preuss has absolutely nothing to do with national sympathies and antipathies.

Recently, H. Bönke has investigated Bergson's “original new philosophical creation,” because Bergson has found it necessary in these fateful times to speak such hate-filled words and to shower such contempt upon German spiritual life (see Bönke's writing: Plagiarizer Bergson, Membre de l'Institut. Answer to the Disparagements of German Science by Edmond Perrier, President de l'Academie des Sciences. Charlottenburg, Huth, 1915). When one considers all that Bönke presents about the way Bergson reproduces what he has gotten from German thought-life, the statements will not seem exaggerated that the philosopher Wundt makes in the “Central Literary Paper of Germany,” number 46, of November 13, 1915: “... Bönke shows no lack ... of incriminating material. The greater part of his book consists of passages, taken from Bergson's and Schopenhauer's works, in which the younger author repeats the thoughts of the older, either verbatim or with slight variation. Even so, this alone is not the decisive point. Therefore, let us be a little bit clearer and more critical in ordering the examples advanced by Bönke. They then fall definitely into three categories. The first contains sentences from both authors that, except for minor differences, coincide exactly. ...” In the other categories the coincidence lies more in the way their thoughts are formed.

Now it is perhaps really not so important to show how much Bergson, who condemns German spiritual life so furiously, reveals himself to be a right willing proponent of this German spiritual life; more important is the fact that Bergson propounds this spiritual life in lightly woven, easily attainable reflections, and that many a critic would have done better to wait with his enthusiastic proclaiming of this “new enlivener” of world views until, through better understanding of those thinkers to whom Bergson owes his stimulus, the critic might have refrained from his proclamation.

That a person be stimulated by his predecessors is a natural thing in the evolution of mankind; what matters, however, is whether the stimulus leads to a process of further development or—and Bönke's presentation also makes this quite clear—leads to a process of regression as in Bergson's case.

A Side Glance

[ 16 ] In 1912 The Lofty Goal of Knowledge by Omar al Raschid Bey was published in Munich. (Please note: The author is not Turkish; he is German; and the view he advocates has nothing to do with Mohammedanism, but is an ancient Indian world view appearing in modern dress.) The book appeared after the author's death. If the author had had the wish to produce in his soul the requirements needed for understanding the series of thinkers depicted in this present book, a book like his would not have appeared in our age, and its author would not have believed he should show to himself and others, by what he said in his book, a path of knowledge appropriate to the present day. But because of the way things appear to him, the author of The Lofty Goal could have only a pitying smile for the assertion just made here. He would not see that everything he presents to our soul experience in his final chapter “Awakening out of Appearances” on the basis of what preceded this chapter and with this chapter, was, in fact, a correct path of knowledge for the ancient Indian. One can understand this path completely as one belonging to the past. The author would not see that this path of knowledge, however, leads into another path if one does not stop prematurely on the first, but rather travels on upon the path of reality in accordance with the spirit as modern idealism has done.

[ 17 ] The author would have to have recognized that his “Awakening out of Appearances” is only an apparent awakening; actually it is a drawing back of oneself—effected by one's own soul experiences—from the appearances, a kind of quaking when faced by the appearances, and therefore not an “awakening out of appearances,” but rather a falling asleep into delusion—a self-delusion that considers its world of delusion to be reality because it cannot get to the point of taking the path into a reality in accordance with the spirit. Planck's self-denying thinking is a soul experience into which al Raschid's deluded thinking cannot penetrate. In The Lofty Goal there is the statement: “Whoever seeks his salvation in this world has fallen prey to this world and remains so; for him there is no escape from unstilled desire; for him there is no escape from vain play; for him there is no escape from the tight fetters of the ‘I’. Whoever does not lift himself out of this world lives and dies with his world.” Before these sentences stand these: “Whoever seeks his salvation in the ‘I,’ for him egoism (Selbstsucht) is a commandment, for him egoism is God.” But whoever recognizes in a living way the motive soul forces that hold sway in the series of thinkers from Fichte up to Planck will see through the deception manifesting in these statements from The Lofty Goal. For he recognizes how the obsession (Sucht) with oneself—egoism—lies before the experience of the “I” in Fichte's sense, and how a fleeing from an acknowledgment of the “I”—in an ancient Indian sense—seemingly leads arrogant cognitive striving farther into the spiritual world, but actually throws one back into obsession with one's “I.” For only the finding of the “I” lets the “I” escape the fetters of obsession with the “I,” the fetters of egoism. The point, in fact, really is whether, in “awakening out of appearances,” one has experiences of The Lofty Goal that are produced by a falling back into an obsession with one's “I,” or whether one has the kind of experiences to which the following words can point. Whoever seeks his salvation in fleeing from the “I” falls prey to obsession with the “I”; whoever finds the “I” frees himself from obsession with the “I”; for, obsession with the “I” makes the “I” into its own idol; finding the “I” gives the “I” to the world. Whoever seeks his salvation in fleeing from the world will be thrown back from the world into his own delusions; he is deluded by an arrogant illusion of knowledge, which lets a vain playing with ideas appear to him as world truth; he looses the fetters of the “I” in front and does not notice how, from behind, the enemy of knowledge binds them all the faster. Whoever, scorning the phenomena of the world, wants to lift himself above the world leads himself into a delusion that holds him all the more securely because it reveals itself to him as wisdom; he leads himself into a delusion by which he holds himself and others back from the difficult awakening in the idealism of modern world views, and dreams into an “awakening out of appearances,” A supposed awakening, like that which The Lofty Goal wishes to indicate, is indeed a source of that experience which ever and again makes the “awakened person” speak of the sublimity of his knowledge; but it is also a hindrance for the experiencing of this idealism in world views. Please do not take these remarks as a wish on the author's part to disparage in any way al Raschid's kind of cognitive striving; what the present author is saying here is an objection that seems necessary for him to raise against a world view that seems to him to live in the worst possible self-delusion. Such an objection can certainly also be raised when one values, from a certain point of view, a manifestation of the spirit; it can seem most necessary precisely there, because that seriousness moves him to do so which must hold sway in dealing with questions of knowledge.

Eine vergessene Strömung im deutschen Gedankenleben

[ 1 ] Fichte, Schelling und Hegel erscheinen in ihrer vollen Bedeutung ganz besonders dem, der auf die weittragenden Anregungen blickt, die sie für Persönlichkeiten hatten, denen eine weit geringere geistige Spannkraft als ihnen selbst eigen war. Es treibt und wirkt etwas in den Seelen dieser Denkerdreiheit, das in ihnen selbst nicht voll zum Ausdruck kommen konnte. Und, was so treibt als Grundton in den Seelen dieser Denker: es wirkt in Nachfolgern lebendig weiter und bringt diese zu geistgemäßen Weltanschauungen, die von den großen Vorgängern selbst nicht erreicht werden konnten, weil diese gewissermaßen ihre seelische Spannkraft in ersten Anläufen erschöpfen mußten.

[ 2 ] So tritt in Johann Gottlieb Fichtes Sohn, Immanuel Hermann Fichte, ein Denker auf, der in das Geistige tiefer einzudringen versucht als sein Vater, und als Schelling und Hegel. Wer einen solchen Versuch wagt, der wird nicht nur von außen her den Widerspruch aller Ängstlichen in Weltanschauungsfragen außer ihm hören; er wird diesen Widerspruch, wenn er besonnener Denker ist, auch aus der eigenen Seele heraus deutlich wahrnehmen. Gibt es denn wirklich eine Möglichkeit, in der Menschenseele Erkenntniskräfte zu entbinden, die in Gebiete führen, aus denen die Sinne keine Anschauung geben? Was kann die Wirklichkeit solcher Gebiete verbürgen, was den Unterschied solcher Wirklichkeit von den Erzeugnissen der Phantasie und Träumerei kennzeichnen? Wer den Geist dieses Widerspruches nicht gewissermaßen wie den treuen Begleiter seiner Besonnenheit stets an seiner Seite hat, der wird mit seinen geisteswissenschaftlichen Versuchen leicht straucheln; wer ihn hat, wird in ihm einen hohen Lebenswert erkennen. - Wer sich in die Ausführungen Immanuel Hermann Fichtes einläßt, wird finden können, daß von seinen großen Vorgängern in ihn eine Geistesart übergegangen ist, die ebenso seine Schritte in das Geistgebiet kräftig macht, wie sie ihm Besonnenheit in dem angedeuteten Sinne verleiht.

[ 3 ] Der Gesichtspunkt Hegelscher Weltanschauung, der die Geistwesenheit der Ideenwelt zur Grundüberzeugung macht, konnte auch für Immanuel Hermann Fichte Ausgangspunkt seiner Gedankenentwickelung sein. Doch empfand er es als Schwäche dieser Weltanschauung, daß sie von ihrem übersinnlichen Gesichtspunkte aus doch nur das schaut, was in der Sinnenwelt offenbar ist. Wer Immanuel Hermann Fichtes Anschauungen nachlebt, der kann etwa das folgende als deren Grundtöne empfinden. Die Seele erlebt sich selbst auf eine übersinnliche Art, wenn sie sich über die Sinnesanschauung zum Weben im Ideenreiche erhebt. Sie hat sich damit nicht nur befähigt, die Sinneswelt anders anzusehen, als die Sinne sie ansehen - was der Hegelschen Weltanschauung entsprechen würde -; sie hat vielmehr dadurch ein Selbsterlebnis, das sie durch nichts haben kann, was in der Sinneswelt zu finden ist. Sie weiß nunmehr von etwas, was selbst übersinnlich an ihr ist. Dieses «Etwas» kann nicht bloß «die Idee» ihres sinnlichen Leibes sein. Es muß vielmehr ein lebendig Wesenhaftes sein, das dem sinnlichen Leib so zugrunde liegt, daß dieser im Sinne seiner Idee gebildet ist. So wird Immanuel Hermann Fichte über den sinnlichen Leib hinaus zu einem übersinnlichen Leib geführt, der aus seinem Leben heraus den ersteren bildet. Hegel schreitet von der Sinnesanschauung zum Denken über die Sinnesanschauung fort. Fichte sucht im Menschen das Wesen, welches das Denken als ein übersinnliches erleben kann. Hegel müßte, wenn er im Denken etwas Übersinnliches sehen will, diesem Denken selber die Fähigkeit des Denkens zuschreiben. Fichte kann das nicht mitmachen. Er muß sich sagen: Soll man nicht den sinnlichen Leib selbst als den Erzeuger der Gedanken ansehen, so ist man gezwungen, über ihn hinaus ein Übersinnliches anzunehmen. Getrieben von einer solchen Anschauung betrachtet Fichte den menschlichen Sinnenleib naturwissenschaftlich (physiologisch), und er findet, daß eine solche Betrachtung, wenn sie nur unbefangen genug ist, genötigt ist, dem sinnlichen Leibe einen übersinnlichen zugrunde zu legen. Im 118. und 119. Paragraph seiner «Anthropologie» (2. Auflage 1860) sagt er darüber: «In den Stoffelementen daher kann das wahrhaft Beharrende, jenes einende Formprinzip des Leibes nicht gefunden werden, welches sich während unseres ganzen Lebens wirksam erweist». - «So werden wir auf eine zweite, wesentlich andere Ursache im Leibe hingewiesen.» - «Indem» dieses «das eigentlich im Stoffwechsel Beharrliche enthält, ist es der wahre, innere, unsichtbare, aber in aller sichtbaren Stofflichkeit gegenwärtige Leib. Das andere, die äußere Erscheinung desselben, aus unablässigem Stoffwechsel gebildet, möge fortan ‹Körper› heißen, der wahrhaft nicht beharrlich und nicht eins, der bloße Effekt oder das Nachbild jener inneren Leiblichkeit ist, welche ihn in die wechselnde Stoffwelt hineinwirft, gleichwie etwa die magnetische Kraft aus den Teilen des Eisenfeilstaubes sich einen scheinbar dichten Körper bereitet, der aber nach allen Seiten zerstäubt, wenn die bindende Gewalt ihm entzogen ist.» Für Fichte ist damit die Aussicht eröffnet, herauszukommen aus der Sinnenwelt, in welcher der Mensch zwischen Geburt und Tod wirkt, in eine übersinnliche Welt, der er durch den unsichtbaren Leib so verknüpft ist, wie der sinnlichen durch den sichtbaren. Denn die Erkenntnis dieses unsichtbaren Leibes bringt ihn zu der Ansicht, die er mit den Worten ausspricht: «Denn kaum braucht hier noch gefragt zu werden, wie der Mensch an sich selbst sich verhalte - in diesem Todesvorgange? Dieser bleibt auch nach dem letzten, uns unsichtbaren Akte des Lebensprozesses in seinem Wesen ganz derselbe nach Geist und Organisationskraft, welcher er vorher war. Seine Integrität ist bewahrt; denn er hat durchaus nichts verloren von dem, was sein war und zu seiner Substanz gehörte während des sichtbaren Lebens. Er kehrt nur im Tode in die unsichtbare Welt zurück, oder vielmehr, da er dieselbe nie verlassen hatte, da sie das eigentlich Beharrende in allem Sichtbaren ist, - er hat nur eine bestimmte Form der Sichtbarkeit abgestreift. ‹Totsein› bedeutet lediglich, der gewöhnlichen Sinnesauffassung nicht mehr perceptibel (wahrnehmbar) bleiben, ganz auf gleiche Weise, wie auch das eigentlich Reale, die letzten Gründe der Körpererscheinungen den Sinnen impereeptibel (unwahrnehmbar) sind.» Und so sicher fühlt sich Fichte mit einem solchen Gedanken in der übersinnlichen Welt stehend, daß er sagen kann: «Mit diesem Begriffe der Seelenfortdauer überspringen wir daher nicht nur die Erfahrung und greifen in ein unbekanntes Gebiet bloß illusorischer Existenzen hinüber, sondern wir befinden uns mit ihm gerade mitten in der begreiflichen, dem Denken zugänglichen Wirklichkeit. Das Gegenteil davon, ein Aufhören der Seele zu behaupten, wäre das Naturwidrige, aller Erfahrungsanalogie Widersprechende. Die ‹gestorbene›, d.h. sinnlich unsichtbar gewordene Seele existiert um nichts weniger, unentrückt ihren ursprünglichen Lebensbedingungen fort. ... Ihrer Organisationskraft muß nur ein anderes Verleiblichungsmittel sich darbieten, um auch in neuer leiblicher Wirksamkeit dazustehen....» (S 133 und S 134 von Fichtes «Anthropologie».)

[ 4 ] Von solchen Anschauungen aus eröffnet sich für Immanuel Hermann Fichte die Möglichkeit einer Selbsterkenntnis des Menschen, die dieser erlangt, wenn er von dem Gesichtspunkt aus sich betrachtet, welchen er gewinnt durch das Erleben in seiner übersinnlichen Wesenheit. Seine sinnliche Wesenheit bringt den Menschen bis zum Denken. Doch im Denken ergreift er sich als übersinnliches Wesen. Erhebt er das bloße Denken zum inneren Erleben, wodurch es nicht mehr bloß Denken ist, sondern übersinnliches Anschauen, so gewinnt er eine Wissensart, durch die er nicht mehr nur auf Sinnliches, sondern Übersinnliches hinschaut. Ist Anthropologie die Wissenschaft vom Menschen, wenn dieser sein in der Sinneswelt befindliches Teil betrachtet, so kommt durch die Anschauung des Übersinnlichen eine andere Wissenschaft zum Vorschein, über die sich Immanuel Hermann Fichte so ausspricht (S 270): «... die Anthropologie endet in dem von den mannigfaltigsten Seiten her begründeten Ergebnisse, daß der Mensch nach der wahren Eigenschaft seines Wesens, wie in der eigentlichen Quelle seines Bewußtseins, einer übersinnlichen Welt angehöre. Das Sinnenbewußtsein dagegen und die auf seinem Augpunkte entstehende phänomenale Welt (Erscheinungswelt) mit dem gesamten, auch menschlichen Sinnenleben, haben keine andere Bedeutung, als nur die Stätte zu sein, in welcher jenes übersinnliche Leben des Geistes sich vollzieht, indem er durch frei bewußte eigene Tat den jenseitigen Geistesgehalt der Ideen in die Sinnenwelt einführt. ...» Diese gründliche Erfassung des Menschenwesens erhebt nunmehr die «Anthropologie» in ihrem Endresultate zur «Anthroposophie».


[ 5 ] Durch Immanuel Hermann Fichte ist der Erkenntnistrieb, der im deutschen Weltanschauungs-Idealismus sich kundgibt, dazu gebracht worden, die ersten derjenigen Schritte zu unternehmen, welche die menschliche Einsicht zu einer Wissenschaft der geistigen Welt führen können. In ähnlicher Art wie Immanuel Hermann Fichte die Ideen seiner Vorgänger: Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Schelling und Hegel weiterzuführen sucht, strebten dasselbe noch viele andere Geister an. Denn dieser deutsche Idealismus deutet auf die Keimkraft zu einer wirklichen Entwickelung derjenigen Erkenntniskräfte des Menschen, die Übersinnlich-Geistiges so schauen wie die Sinne Sinnlich-Stoffliches schauen. Hier soll nur auf einige dieser Geister der Blick gewendet werden. Wie fruchtbar sich die deutsche idealistische Geistesströmung nach dieser Richtung hin erweist, sieht man, wenn man nicht bloß auf diejenigen Geister deutet, die in den gebräuchlichen Handbüchern über Philosophie-Geschichte behandelt werden, sondern auch auf solche, deren geistiges Wirken in engere Grenzen eingeschlossen war. Es gibt zum Beispiel «Kleine Schriften» von dem am 16. August 1867 in Bromberg als Gymnasialdirektor verstorbenen Johann Heinrich Deinhardt (Hermann Schmidt hat diese Schriften 1869 in Leipzig, bei B.G. Teubner, herausgegeben). Man findet darin Aufsätze über «den Gegensatz des Pantheismus und des Deismus in den vorchristlichen Religionen», über «den Begriff der Religion», über «Kepler, Leben und Charakter» usw. Der Grundton dieser Abhandlungen ist durchaus ein solcher, der zeigt, wie ihres Verfassers Gedankenleben im deutschen Weltanschauungs-Idealismus wurzelt. Einer der Aufsitze spricht über die «Vernunftgründe für die Unsterblichkeit der menschlichen Seele». Dieser Aufsatz verteidigt die Unsterblichkeit zunächst nur mit den Gründen, die sich dem gewöhnlichen Denken ergeben. Allein am Schlusse findet sich die folgende bedeutungsvolle Anmerkung des Herausgebers: «Der Verfasser hatte nach einem Briefe an den Herausgeber vom 14. August 1866 die Absicht, diese Abhandlung bei der Gesamtausgabe seiner gesammelten kleinen Schriften durch eine Bemerkung über den neuen Leib, den sich die Seele schon in diesem Leben ausarbeitete, zu erweitern. Sein im Jahr darauf erfolgender Tod verhinderte die Ausführung dieses Plans.» Wie wirft eine solche Bemerkung ein Streiflicht auf die Anregungen, die vom deutschen Weltanschauungs-Idealismus aus die Geister trieben, in wissenschaftlicher Art in das Geistgebiet einzudringen! Wie viele derartige Versuche würde gegenwärtig jemand auffinden, der nur allein denjenigen nachginge, die in der Literatur noch zu finden sind! Wie viele lassen sie vermuten, die nicht für die Literatur, wohl aber für das Leben ihre Früchte getragen haben! Man blickt da auf eine in dem gegenwärtig herrschenden wissenschaftlichen Zeitbewußtsein wirklich mehr oder weniger vergessene Strömung des deutschen Geisteslebens.

[ 6 ] Einer derjenigen Geister, von denen heute kaum gesprochen wird, ist Ignaz Paul Vitalis Troxler. Aus der Reihe seiner zahlreichen Schriften seien hier nur genannt seine 1835 erschienenen «Vorlesungen über Philosophie». Durch sie spricht sich eine Persönlichkeit aus, die durchaus ein Bewußtsein davon hat, wie der Mensch, der sich bloß seiner Sinne und des mit den Beobachtungen der Sinne rechnenden Verstandes bedient, nur einen Teil der Welt erkennen kann. Auch Troxler fühlt sich wie Immanuel Hermann Fichte mit dem Denken in einer übersinnlichen Welt drinnenstehend. Aber er empfindet auch, wie der Mensch, wenn er sich der Kraft entrückt, die ihn an die Sinne bindet, nicht nur sich vor eine Welt stellen kann, die im Hegelschen Sinne erdacht ist, sondern wie er durch diese Entrückung in seinem inneren Wesen das Aufblühen von rein geistigen Erkenntnismitteln erlebt, durch die er eine geistige Welt geistig schaut, wie die Sinne die Sinnenwelt sinnlich schauen. Von einem «übergeistigen Sinn» spricht Troxler. Und man kann sich auf folgende Art eine Vorstellung von dem bilden, was er damit meint. Der Mensch beobachtet die Dinge der Welt durch seine Sinne. Dadurch erhält er sinnliche Bilder von den Dingen. Er denkt dann über diese Bilder nach. Dadurch erschließen sich ihm Gedanken, die nicht mehr das Sinnlich-Bildhafte in sich tragen. Der Mensch fügt also durch die Kraft seines Geistes zu den Sinnesbildern die übersinnlichen Gedanken hinzu. Erlebt er sich nun in der Wesenheit, die in ihm denkt, so daß er über das bloße Denken zu geistigem Erleben aufsteigt, dann ergreift ihn von diesem Erleben aus eine innere rein geistige Kraft des Verbildlichens. Er schaut dann eine Welt in Bildern, die übersinnlich erlebter Wirklichkeit als Offenbarung dienen kann. Diese Bilder sind nicht von den Sinnen empfangen; aber sie sind lebensvoll wie die Sinnesbilder; sie sind nicht Ergebnisse einer Träumerei, sondern die von der Seele bildhaft festgehaltenen Erlebnisse in der übersinnlichen Welt. Im gewöhnlichen Erkennen liegt zuerst das Sinnbild vor, und der Gedanke kommt hinzu im Erkenntnisvorgange - der Gedanke, der nicht sinnlich-bildhaft ist. Im geistigen Erkenntnisvorgange liegt das übersinnliche Erlebnis vor; dieses könnte als solches nicht angeschaut werden, wenn es sich nicht durch eine dem Geist naturgemäße Kraft in das Bild ergösse, das sie zur geistig-anschaulichen Versinnlichung bringt. Ein solches Erkennen ist für Trox1er das des «übergeistigen Sinnes». Und die Bilder dieses übergeistigen Sinnes werden durch den «übersinnlichen Geist» des Menschen so ergriffen, wie in der Sinneserkenntnis die sinnlichen Bilder durch die Vernunft. In dem Zusammenwirken von übersinnlichem Geist mit übergeistigem Sinn entwickelt sich, nach Troxlers Anschauung, das Geisterkennen (vergleiche dazu die sechste der «Vorlesungen über Philosophie» von Troxler).—Von solchen Voraussetzungen ausgehend, erahnt Troxler in dem Menschen, der in der Sinneswelt sich erlebt, einen «höheren Menschen», der diesem zugrunde liegt, und der der übersinnlichen Welt angehört; und er fühlt sich in dieser Meinung im Einklange mit dem, was Friedrich Schlegel ausgesprochen hat. Und so werden ihm wie schon früher Friedrich Schlegel die höchsten in der Sinneswelt sich offenbarenden Eigenschaften und Betätigungen des Menschen zum Ausdrucke von Fähigkeiten des übersinnlichen Menschen. Indem der Mensch in der Sinneswelt steht, eignet seiner Seele die Glaubenskraft. Doch ist diese eben nur die Offenbarung der übersinnlichen Seele durch den sinnlichen Leib. Im Übersinnlichen liegt der Glaubenskraft eine Fähigkeit der Seele zugrunde, die man - will man sie übersinnlich-bildhaft ausdrücken - ein Gehör des übersinnlichen Menschen nennen muß. Und so ist es mit der Kraft des Hoffens. Ihr liegt ein Sehen des übersinnlichen Menschen zugrunde; der Betätigung in Liebe entspricht im «höheren Menschen» die Fähigkeit, im Geiste zu «tasten», zu berühren, wie der Gefühlssinn in der sinnlichen Welt die Fähigkeit des Tastens ist. Troxler spricht sich darüber (auf Seite 107 seiner «Vorlesungen über Philosophie», Bern 1835) in folgender Art aus: «Sehr schön und wahr» hat das Verhältnis des Sinnes- zum Geistesmenschen «unser verewigter Freund, Friedrich Schlegel» ins Licht gesetzt. In seinen Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Sprache und des Wortes sagt er: «Will man in jenem Alphabet des Bewußtseins, welches die einzelnen Elemente zu den einzelnen Silben und ganzen Worten hergibt, wieder die ersten Anfänge unserer höheren Erkenntnis finden, nachdem Gott selbst den Schlußstein des höchsten Bewußtseins bildet, so muß das Gefühl des Geistes, als der lebendige Mittelpunkt des gesamten Bewußtseins, und als Vereinigungspunkt mit dem höheren angenommen werden. ... Man pflegt diese Grundgefühle des Ewigen sehr häufig als Glauben, Hoffnung und Liebe zu bezeichnen. ... Sind jene drei Grundgefühle, oder Eigenschaften, oder Zustände im Bewußtsein, als ebenso viele Erkenntnis- und Wahrnehmungs- oder wenn man lieber will, wenigstens Ahnungsorgane des Göttlichen zu betrachten, so darf man sie in dieser Hinsicht, und in Beziehung auf die einem jeden derselben eigentümliche Auffassungsform wohl mit den äußeren Sinnen und Sinneswerkzeugen vergleichen. Da entspricht denn die Liebe in der ersten erregenden Seelenberührung, in der fortwährenden Anziehung, und endlich vollkommenen Vereinigung auffallend dem äußeren Gefühlssinn; der Glaube ist das innere Gehör des Geistes, welches das gegebene Wort einer höheren Mitteilung vereint, auffaßt und in sich bewahrt; die Hoffnung aber ist das Auge, dessen Licht die mit tiefem Verlangen ersehnten Gegenstände schon aus der weiten Ferne erblickt.» Daß nun Troxler über den Sinn, den Schlegel diesen Sätzen gegeben, hinausgeht und durchaus sie in dem Sinne denkt, wie oben angedeutet ist, das zeigen schon die Worte, die er hinzusetzt: «Weit über Verstand und Wille, wie deren Wechselwirkung, weit über Vernunft und Freiheit, und ihre Einheit sind diese in einem Bewußtsein von Geist und Herz sich einenden Gemütsideen erhaben, und wie Verstand und Wille, Vernunft und Freiheit, und alle unter ihnen liegenden seelischen Fähigkeiten und Vermögen eine erdwärts gewandte Reflexion darstellen, sind diese drei ein himmelwärts gerichtetes Bewußtsein, das von einem wahrhaft göttlichen Lichte erleuchtet wird.» Ein gleiches zeigt sich dadurch, daß auch Troxler sich über den übersinnlichen Seelenleib ganz in der Art ausspricht, die bei Immanuel Hermann Fichte anzutreffen ist: «Schon früher haben die Philosophen einen feinen, hehren Seelleib unterschieden von dem gröberen Körper ... eine Seele, die ein Bild des Leibes an sich habe, das sie Schema nannten, und das ihnen der innere höhere Mensch war.... In der neuesten Zeit selbst Kant in den Träumen eines Geistersehers träumt ernsthaft im Scherze einen ganzen inwendigen seelischen Menschen, der alle Gliedmaßen des auswendigen an seinem Geisterleib trage; Lavater dichtet und denkt ebenso; und selbst, wenn Jean Paul humoristisch über das Bonetsche Unterziehröckchen und das Platnersche Seelenschnürleibchen scherzt, die im gröberen Körperüberrock und Marterkittel stecken sollen, so hören wir ihn doch auch wieder fragen, ‹wozu und woher wurden diese außerordentlichen Anlagen und Wünsche in uns gelegt, die bloß wie verschluckte Diamanten unsere erdige Hülle langsam zerschneiden? ... In den steinernen Gliedern (des Menschen) wachsen und reifen seine lebendigen nach einer uns unbekannten Lebensweise›. Wir könnten» - sagt Troxler weiter - «noch eine Unzahl ähnlicher Denk- und Dichtweisen anführen, welche am Ende nur verschiedene Anschauungen und Vorstellungen sind, in welchen ... die wahre, einzige Lehre von der Individualität und Unsterblichkeit des Menschen enthalten» ist.

[ 7 ] Auch Troxler spricht davon, daß auf dem von ihm gesuchten Erkenntniswege eine Wissenschaft vom Menschen möglich ist, durch die - um seine eigenen Ausdrücke zu gebrauchen - der «übergeistige Sinn» im Verein mit dem «übersinnlichen Geist» die übersinnliche Wesenheit des Menschen in einer «Anthroposophie» erfassen. Auf 5.101 seiner «Vorlesungen» findet sich der Satz: «Wenn es nun höchst erfreulich ist, daß die neueste Philosophie, welche ... in jeder Anthroposophie ... sich offenbaren muß, emporwindet, so ist doch nicht zu übersehen, daß diese Idee nicht eine Frucht der Spekulation sein kann, und die wahrhafte Individualität des Menschen weder mit dem, was sie als subjektiven Geist oder endliches Ich aufstellt, noch mit dem, was sie als absoluten Geist oder absolute Persönlichkeit diesem gegenüberstellt, verwechselt werden darf.»

[ 8 ] Es ist kein Zweifel, daß Troxler mehr in einem dunklen Gefühle als in einer klaren Anschauung den Weg über Hegels Gedankenwelt hinaus gesucht hat. Dennoch kann man in seinem Erkenntnisleben beobachten, wie die Anregungen des deutschen Weltanschauungsidealismus Fichtes, Schellings, Hegels bei einer Persönlichkeit wirken, die nicht die Ansichten dieser Denker-Dreiheit zu den ihrigen machen kann; die aber ihre eigenen Wege dadurch findet, daß sie diese Anregungen empfängt.


[ 9 ] Zu den vergessenen, ja schon während ihres Lebens unbeachteten Persönlichkeiten der deutschen Geistesentwickelung gehört Karl Christian Planck. Geboren ist er 1819 in Stuttgart, gestorben 1880; er war Professor am Gymnasium in Ulm, später am Seminar in Blaubeuren. Noch 1877 hoffte er, daß man ihm den damals frei gewordenen philosophischen Lehrstuhl in Tübingen übertragen werde. Es geschah nicht. In einer Reihe von Schriften sucht er sich einer Weltanschauung zu nähern, welche ihm als der Ausdruck der geistigen Art des deutschen Volkes erschien. In seinem Buche «Grundlinien einer Wissenschaft der Natur» (1864) spricht er aus, wie er mit den eigenen Gedanken die Gedanken der forschenden deutschen Volksseele darstellen will: «Welche Macht tiefgewurzelter Vorurteile von der bisherigen Anschauung aus seiner - des Verfassers - Schrift entgegensteht, dessen ist er sich vollkommen bewußt; allein, wie schon die Arbeit selbst, trotz aller Ungunst der Umstände, die zufolge der ganzen Lage und Berufsstellung des Verfassers einem Werk dieser Art sich entgegenstellte, doch ihre Durchführung und ihren Weg in die Öffentlichkeit sich erkämpft hat, so ist er auch gewiß, daß das, was sich jetzt erst seine Anerkennung erkämpfen muß, einst als die einfachste und selbstverständlichste Wahrheit erscheinen wird, und daß darin nicht bloß seine Sache, sondern die wahrhaft deutsche Anschauung der Dinge über alle noch unwürdig äußerliche und undeutsche Auffassung der Natur und des Geistes siegen wird. - Was in unbewußter tiefsinniger Ahnung schon unsere mittelalterliche Dichtung vorgebildet hat, das wird endlich in der Reife der Zeiten an unserer Nation sich erfüllen. Die unpraktische, mit Schaden und Spott heimgesuchte Innerlichkeit deutschen Geistes (wie Wolfram sie in seinem Parzival schildert) erringt endlich in der Kraft ihres unablässigen Strebens das Höchste; sie schaut den letzten einfachen Gesetzen der Dinge und des menschlichen Daseins selbst auf den Grund; und was die Dichtung phantastisch mittelalterlich in den Wundern des Grals versinnbildlicht hat, dessen Herrschaft ihr Held erringt, das erhält umgekehrt seine rein natürliche Erfüllung und Wirklichkeit in der bleibenden Erkenntnis der Natur und des Geistes selbst.» - In der letzten Zeit seines Lebens faßte Karl Christian Planck sein Gedankenwerk zusammen in einem Buche, das 1881 der Philosoph Karl Köstlin als das «Testament eines Deutschen» herausgegeben hat.

[ 10 ] Es ist durchaus eine ähnliche Art von Empfindung des Erkenntnisrätsels in Plancks Seele wahrzunehmen, wie sie bei den andern in dieser Schrift charakterisierten Denkerpersönlichkeiten sich offenbart. Dies Erkenntnisrätsel in seiner ursprünglichen Gestalt wird für Planck Ausgangspunkt seines Forschens. Ist im Umkreis der menschlichen Gedankenwelt die Kraft zu finden, durch die der Mensch die wahre Wirklichkeit erfassen kann, die Wirklichkeit, die seinem Dasein Sinn und Bedeutung im Weltendasein gibt? In die Natur sieht sich der Mensch hinein- und ihr gegenübergestellt. Er kann sich über das, was in deren Tiefen als wahre Wesenkräfte waltet, wohl Gedanken machen; allein wo ist, was ihm dafür bürgt, daß seine Gedanken irgend eine andere Bedeutung haben, als daß sie Geschöpfe seiner eigenen Seele, ohne Verwandtschaft mit jenen Tiefen sind? Wären sie dieses, so müßte dem Menschen ja unbekannt bleiben, was er selbst ist und wie er in der wahren Welt wurzelt. Durch irgendeine andre Seelenkraft als durch das Denken sich den Weltentiefen nahen zu wollen, lag Planck so fern wie Hegel. Er konnte keine andere Ansicht haben als die, dem Denken müsse sich die echte Wirklichkeit irgendwie ergeben. Aber wie weit man auch ausgreift mit dem Denken, wie man auch die innere Kraft desselben zu erstarken sucht: man bleibt ja doch immer nur im Denken; man stößt in den Weiten und Tiefen des Denkens auf kein Sein. Durch seine eigene Wesenheit scheint sich das Denken von jeder Gemeinschaft mit dem Sein auszuschließen. Doch der Einblick in diese Seinsfremdheit des Denkens wird für Planck nun eben der Lichtstrahl, der ihm lösend auf das Welträtsel fällt. Wenn das Denken gar nicht Anspruch darauf macht, selbst irgendwie etwas von der Wirklichkeit in sich zu tragen, wenn es wahrheitsgemäß sich als das Unwirkliche offenbart, dann erweist es sich doch gerade dadurch als das Werkzeug, um die Wirklichkeit auszudrücken. Wäre es selbst ein Wirkliches, dann könnte die Seele nur in seiner Wirklichkeit weben, und käme aus ihr nicht heraus; ist es selbst unwirklich, dann stört es die Seele durch seine eigene Wirklichkeit nicht; der Mensch ist, indem er denkt, gar nicht in einer Gedankenwirklichkeit, sondern in der Gedankenunwirklichkeit, die eben deshalb dem Menschen sich nicht aufdrängt mit ihrer eigenen Wirklichkeit, sondern die Wirklichkeit ausdrückt, von der sie spricht. Wer im Denken selbst etwas Wirkliches sieht, der muß, nach Plancks Ansicht, auf ein Herankommen an die Wirklichkeit verzichten; denn ihm muß sich das Denken zwischen die Seele und die Wirklichkeit stellen. Ist das Denken selbst nichts, kann es also auch dem Erkennen die Wirklichkeit nicht verbergen, so muß diese im Denken sich offenbaren können.

[ 11 ] Mit dieser Ansicht hat Planck zunächst nur den Ausgangspunkt für seine Weltanschauung gewonnen. Denn in dem Gedankenweben, das die Seele im Leben unmittelbar hat, ist keineswegs das reine, sich selbst verleugnende, ja sich verneinende Denken wirksam. Da hinein spielt, was im Vorstellen, Fühlen, Wollen, Wünschen der Seele lebt. Weil dies so ist, entstehen die Trübungen der Weltanschauung. Und Plancks Streben ist, eine solche Weltanschauung zu erringen, in der alles, was sie enthält, Ergebnis des Denkens ist, aber nichts aus dem Denken selbst stammt. In allem, was zu einem Gedanken über die wirkliche Welt gemacht wird, muß auf das geschaut werden, was im Denken lebt, ohne selbst erdacht zu sein. Planck malt sein Weltbild mit einem Denken, das sich selbst aufgibt, um die Welt aus sich leuchten zu lassen.

[ 12 ] Als Beispiel wie Planck in solchem Streben zu einem Weltbild gelangen will, sei mit einigen Strichen gekennzeichnet, wie er über das Wesen der Erde denkt. - Wenn jemand die Erde so vorstellt, wie die rein physische Geologie das mit sich bringt, so ist in dieser Vorstellung für Plancks Weltanschauung keine Wahrheit. So die Erde vorzustellen, wäre wie wenn man von einem Baum sprechen wollte und nur den Holzstamm ohne Blätter, Blüten und Früchte im Auge hätte. Ein solcher Stamm kann für den Anblick der physischen Augen Wirklichkeit genannt werden. Im höheren Sinne ist er keine Wirklichkeit. Denn er kann, so wie er ist, im Weltenzusammenhang für sich nicht vorkommen. Er kann das nur sein, was er ist, indem zugleich die Triebkräfte in ihm entstehen, die Blätter, Blüten und Früchte entfalten. Man muß in der Wirklichkeit des Stammes diese Triebkräfte mitdenken und muß sich bewußt sein, daß der bloße Stamm nur ein über sich selbst täuschendes Wirklichkeitsbild gibt. Daß irgend etwas vor den Sinnen da ist, das ist noch kein Beweis, daß es so auch eine Wirklichkeit ist. Die Erde als die Gesamtheit dessen vorgestellt, was sie an mineralischen Gebilden und innerhalb dieser Gebilde vorkommenden Tatsachen zeigt, ist keine Wirklichkeit. Wer Wirkliches über die Erde vorstellen will, der muß sie so vorstellen, daß ihr Mineralreich schon in sich enthält das Pflanzenreich, wie das Stammgebilde des Baumes die Blätter und Blüten; ja daß in der «wahren Erde» schon das Tierreich und der Mensch mit drinnen sind. Man sage nicht, das sei doch eine Selbstverständlichkeit, und im Grunde täusche sich Planck doch nur darüber, daß dies doch jeder ebenso halte wie er. Planck müßte darauf erwidern: wo ist der, der dies tut? Gewiß stellen alle die Erde als den Weltkörper vor mit seinen Pflanzen, Tieren und Menschen. Aber sie stellen eben die mineralische Erde vor, aus ihren geologischen Schichten bestehend, aus ihrer Oberfläche heraus die Pflanzen wachsend, auf ihr die Tiere und Menschen herumwandelnd. Aber diese Summenerde, aus Mineralien, Pflanzen, Tieren und Menschen addiert, gibt es gar nicht. Die ist bloß ein Trugbild der Sinne. Dafür gibt es eine wahre Erde, die ist ein ganz übersinnliches Gebilde, ein unsichtbares Wesen, das aus sich heraus den mineralischen Untergrund sich gibt; sich aber nicht in diesem erschöpft, sondern in dem Pflanzenreiche weiter sich offenbart, dann im Tierreiche, dann im Menschenreiche. Für das Mineralreich, das Pflanzen-, das Tier-, das Menschenreich hat nur derjenige den richtigen Blick, der das Ganze der Erde in seiner Übersinnlichkeit schaut, und der fühlt, wie zum Beispiel die Vorstellung des stofflichen Mineralreiches für sich, ohne die Vorstellung der Seelenentwickelung der Menschheit ein Truggebilde ist. Gewiß, man kann ein stoffliches Mineralreich vorstellen; aber man lebt in der Weltenlüge und nicht in der Weltenwahrheit, wenn man dabei nicht das Gefühl hat, mit einer solchen Vorstellung webt man in dem gleichen Wahn, wie wenn man sich denken wollte, ein Mensch, dem der Kopf abgeschlagen ist, werde weiter ruhig durchs Leben wandeln.—Es könnte gesagt werden: Wenn wahrhafte Erkenntnis das hier Angedeutete notwendig mache, dann könnte diese doch niemals erreicht werden; denn wer behauptet, die mineralische Erde sei keine Wirklichkeit, weil sie im Ganzen der Erde geschaut werden müsse, der sollte auch sagen, das Ganze der Erde müsse wieder im Pflanzensystem und so weiter geschaut werden. Wer solchen Einwand macht, hat den Sinn dessen aber nicht erfaßt, das einer geistgemäßen Weltanschauung zugrunde liegt. Es handelt sich nämlich bei allem Erkennen nicht bloß darum, daß man richtig, sondern das man auch wirklichkeitsgemäß denke. Wer von einem Gemälde spricht, kann wohl sagen, man denke nicht wirklichkeitsgemäß, wenn man nur auf eine Person blicke, während drei auf dem Gemälde sind; aber es kann diese Behauptung innerhalb ihrer Tragweite nicht damit widerlegt werden, daß man sagt: niemand verstehe dies Gemälde, der nicht auch alle vorhergehenden desselben Malers kenne. Zum Erkennen der Wirklichkeit ist eben richtiges und wirklichkeitsgemäßes Denken nötig. Das Mineral als Mineral, die Pflanze als Pflanze und so weiter für sich betrachten, kann wirklichkeitsgemäß sein; die mineralische Erde ist kein wirkliches, sondern ein Phantasiegebilde; auch wenn man sich bewußt ist, daß sie nur ein Teil alles Irdischen ist.—Das ist das Bedeutsame bei einer solchen Persönlichkeit wie Planck, daß sie sich in eine Stimmung bringt, durch die sie die Wahrheit eines Gedankens nicht ersinnt, sondern erlebt. Daß sie in der eigenen Seele eine Kraft für sich entfaltet, durch die sie erlebt, wann ein Gedanke nicht gedacht werden darf, weil er sich durch seine eigene Wesenheit ertötet. Das Dasein einer Wirklichkeit zu ergreifen, die ihr eigenes Leben und ihren eigenen Tod in sich trägt, gehört zu solcher Seelenverfassung, die nicht sich auf die Sinneswelt verläßt, daß die ihr sage: dies ist, oder dies ist nicht.

[ 13 ] Von diesem Gesichtspunkte aus hat Planck denkend zu begreifen gesucht, was in den Naturerscheinungen, was im Menschendasein lebt, im geschichtlichen, im künstlerischen, im Rechtsleben. Er hat in einem geistvollen Buche über die «Wahrheit und Flachheit des Darwinismus» geschrieben. Dieses Werk nennt er einen «Denkstein zur Geschichte heutiger (1872) deutscher Wissenschaft». Es gibt Menschen, die einer Persönlichkeit wie Planck gegenüber die Empfindung haben, eine solche schwebe in weltfremden Begriffshöhen und habe keinen Sinn für das praktische Leben. Dieses erfordere Menschen, die sich am «wirklichen» Leben  - wie man es nennt - ihr gesundes Urteil bilden. Nun, man kann solcher Empfindung gegenüber auch die Meinung haben: vieles stünde anders im wirklichen Leben, wenn diese behäbige Ansicht vom Leben und der Lebenspraxis in der Wirklichkeit sich weniger breit machte. Wenn dagegen die Meinung sich etwas mehr verbreiten könnte, daß Denker wie Planck, weil sie sich eine Seelenverfassung erwerben, durch die sie mit der wahren Wirklichkeit sich verbinden, auch über die Verhältnisse des Lebens ein wahreres Urteil haben als diejenigen, welche sie Begriffsschwärmer und unpraktische Philosophen nennen. Die Meinung ist auch möglich, daß die solcher angeblichen «Begriffsschwärmerei» abholden, sich so recht lebenspraktisch dünkenden Stumpflinge die Witterung für die wahren Verhältnisse des Lebens verlieren, während sie bei den unpraktischen Philosophen gerade zur Treffsicherheit herangezogen wird. Man kann zu einer solchen Meinung kommen, wenn man Planck betrachtet und bei ihm mit der Höhe philosophischer Ideenbildung verbunden sieht ein weitschauendes, treffendes Urteil für die Bedürfnisse echter Lebenspraxis und für die Geschehnisse des äußeren Lebens. Auch wenn man über manches, was Planck an Ideen über äußere Lebensgestaltung entwickelt hat, anderer Ansicht ist als er - was auch bei dem Verfasser dieser Schrift zutrifft -, so kann man doch zugestehen, daß seine Anschauungen gerade auf diesem Gebiete einen lebenstüchtigen Ausgangspunkt für praktische Fragen abgeben können, von dem weitergeschritten werden kann; selbst wenn das Weiterschreiten zu ganz anderem führt, als wovon ausgegangen wird. Und man sollte meinen: Menschen, die in solcher Art «Begriffsschwärmer» sind und eben dadurch durchschauen, welche Kräfte in dem wirklichen Leben tätig sind, taugten für die Bedürfnisse dieses wirklichen Lebens doch besser als mancher, der sich mit Lebenspraxis gerade deshalb gesättigt glaubt, weil er, nach seiner Ansicht, sich durch die Berührung mit irgend einer Ideenwelt nicht hat «dumm machen lassen».—(Über die Stellung Karl Christian Plancks in der Weltanschauungsentwickelung der neueren Zeit hat sich der Verfasser dieser Schrift in seinem 1900 erschienenen Buche «Welt- und Lebensanschauungen im neunzehnten Jahrhundert» ausgesprochen, das unter dem Titel «Die Rätsel der Philosophie» 1914 in neuer Auflage erschienen ist.) Es könnte jemand meinen, es sei ungerechtfertigt, Plancks Gedanken als bedeutsam anzusehen für die Triebkräfte der deutschen Volkheit, da diese Gedanken doch wenig Verbreitung gefunden haben. Eine solche Meinung verkennt, worauf es ankommt, wenn von Wirkung der Volkswesenheit in den Anschauungen der Denker eines Volkes die Rede ist. Was da wirkt, sind die unpersönlichen (oft unterbewußten) Kräfte der Volkheit, die in den Betätigungen des Volkes auf den mannigfaltigsten Gebieten des Daseins leben und die auch in einem solchen Denker die Ideen gestalten. Diese Kräfte waren vor seinem Auftreten da, sind nach demselben wirksam; sie leben, auch wenn nicht von ihnen gesprochen wird; sie leben auch, wenn sie verkannt werden. Und es kann sein, daß sie in einem solchen volksbodenständigen Denker in besonders starker Art wirken, von dem nicht gesprochen wird, weil bis in die Meinungen, die man sich über ihn bildet, weniger hineinstrahlt, was solche Kräfte bergen, als in seine Gedanken. Ein solcher Denker kann oftmals einsam stehen nicht nur während seines Lebens, und auch seine Gedanken können einsam stehen in den Meinungen der Nachwelt. Hat man aber die Eigenart seiner Gedanken erfaßt, dann hat man einen Wesenszug der Volksseele erkannt, einen Zug, der in ihm Gedanke geworden ist, und der unverwüstlich bleibt in der Volkheit; bereit in immer neuen Trieben sich zu offenbaren. Unabhängig von der Frage: was ihm gegönnt war, zu wirken, ist die andere: was in ihm gewirkt hat? Und was immer wieder zu gleich gerichteten Leistungen führen wird? Das «Testament eines Deutschen» von Karl Christian Planck ist 1912 in zweiter Auflage neu herausgegeben worden. Es ist schade, daß manches schreibselige Philosophengemüt damals mehr Begeisterung aufbrachte für die leichtgewobenen und für anspruchslose Seelen deshalb auch leichter verständlichen Weltanschauungsgedanken Henri Bergsons als für die streng gefügten, weitausgreifenden Ideen Plancks. Was ist doch alles geschrieben worden über die «Neugestaltung» der Weltanschauung durch Bergson, namentlich von solchen, die die Neuheit einer Weltanschauung so leicht entdecken, weil ihnen das Verständnis, manchmal sogar die Kenntnis dessen fehlt, was längst dagewesen ist. Bezüglich der «Neuheit» einer der Hauptideen Bergsons hat der Verfasser dieser Schrift ebenfalls in seinem Buche «Rätsel der Philosophie» auf den folgenden wichtigen Tatbestand hingewiesen. (Nebenbei nur sei bemerkt, daß dieser Hinweis vor dem gegenwärtigen Kriege geschrieben ist. Vergleiche das Vorwort des zweiten Bandes des genannten Buches.)—Bergson wird durch seine Gedanken zu einem Umgestalten der verbreiteten Entwickelungsidee für organische Wesen geführt. Er setzt nicht an den Anfang dieser Entwickelung das einfachste Lebewesen, um dann durch äußerliche Kräfte aus diesem die komplizierteren bis herauf zum Menschen hervorgehend zu denken, sondern er stellt sich vor, daß im Ausgangspunkte der Entwickelung ein Wesen stehe, das in irgend einer Form den Antrieb schon enthält, Mensch zu werden. Es kann aber diesen Antrieb nur dadurch zur Verwirklichung bringen, daß es andere Antriebe, die auch in ihm liegen, zuerst aus sich abscheidet. Es gewinnt in der Abscheidung der niederen Lebenswesen die Kraft zur Verwirklichung der höheren. So ist der Mensch seiner Wesenheit nach nicht das zuletzt Entstandene, sondern das zuerst, vor allem anderen Wirksame. Er scheidet aus seinen Bildekräften zuerst die anderen Wesen ab, um in dieser Vorarbeit die Kraft zu seinem Hervortreten in die äußere sinnliche Wirklichkeit zu gewinnen. Selbstverständlich wird da mancher einwenden: nun, daß in der Entwickelung der Lebewesen ein innerer Entwickelungstrieb wirkt, haben doch schon Viele gedacht. Und man wird anführen können den längst vorhandenen Gedanken der Zielstrebigkeit; oder Anschauungen, die Naturforscher wie Nägeli und andere gehabt haben. Solche Einwände treffen aber in einem Falle, wie der hier in Frage kommende ist, nicht das Ziel. Denn bei dem Bergsonschen Gedanken handelt es sich nicht darum, von einer allgemeinen Idee einer inneren Entwickelungskraft auszugehen, sondern von einer bestimmten Vorstellung von dem, was der Mensch in seinem vollen Umfange ist; und aus dieser Vorstellung zu ersehen, daß dieser übersinnlich gedachte Mensch in sich die Antriebe hat, die anderen Naturwesen zuerst in die sinnliche Wirklichkeit zu setzen und dann auch sich in diese hineinzustellen.

[ 14 ] Nun liegt das Folgende vor. Was bei Bergson in schillernder, leichtgeschürzter Ideenentwickelung zu lesen ist, das hat vorher in gedankenstarker, kraftvoller Art der deutsche Denker Wilhelm Heinrich Preuß zum Ausdrucke gebracht. Preuß ist nun auch eine derjenigen Persönlichkeiten, die der hier geschilderten mehr oder weniger vergessenen Strömung einer geistgemäßen deutschen Weltanschauungsentwickelung angehören. Mit machtvollem Wirklichkeitssinn verbindet Preuß Natur- und Weltanschauung - zum Beispiel in seinem Buche «Geist und Stoff» (1882). Den angeführten Bergsonschen Gedanken findet man bei ihm so ausgedrückt: «Es dürfte ... an der Zeit sein, eine ... Lehre von der Entstehung der organischen Arten aufzustellen, welche sich nicht allein auf einseitig aufgestellte Sätze aus der beschreibenden Naturwissenschaft gründet, sondern auch mit den übrigen Naturgesetzen, welche zugleich auch die Gesetze des menschlichen Denkens sind, in voller Übereinstimmung ist. Eine Lehre zugleich, die alles Hypothesierens bar ist und nur auf strengen Schlüssen aus naturwissenschaftlichen Beobachtungen im weitesten Sinne beruht; eine Lehre, die den Artbegriff nach tatsächlicher Möglichkeit rettet, aber zugleich den von Darwin aufgestellten Begriff der Entwickelung hinübernimmt auf ihr Gebiet und fruchtbar zu machen sucht.—Der Mittelpunkt dieser neuen Lehre nun ist der Mensch, die nur einmal auf unserem Planeten wiederkehrende Spezies: Homo sapiens. Merkwürdig, daß die älteren Beobachter bei den Naturgegenständen anfingen und sich dann dermaßen verirrten, daß sie den Weg zum Menschen nicht fanden, was ja auch Darwin nur in kümmerlichster und durchaus unbefriedigender Weise gelang, indem er den Stammvater des Herrn der Schöpfung unter den Tieren suchte - während der Naturforscher bei sich als Menschen anfangen müßte, um so fortschreitend durch das ganze Gebiet des Seins und Denkens zur Menschheit zurückzukehren ... Es war nicht Zufall, daß die menschliche Natur aus der irdischen hervorging, sondern Notwendigkeit. Der Mensch ist das Ziel der tellurischen Vorgänge, und jede andere neben ihm auftauchende Form hat aus der seinigen ihre Züge entlehnt. Der Mensch ist das erstgeborene Wesen des ganzen Kosmos ... Als seine Keime entstanden waren, hatte der gebliebene organische Rückstand nicht die nötige Kraft mehr, um weitere menschliche Keime zu erzeugen. Was noch entstand, wurde Tier oder Pflanze ...»

[ 15 ] Die Idee, wie sie vom Wesen des Menschen in der Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus lebt, leuchtet auch aus diesen Vorstellungen des wenig gekannten Denkers von Elsfleth, Wilhelm Heinrich Preuß. Mit dieser Anschauung weiß er den Darwinismus, sofern dieser nur auf die in der Sinneswelt sich abspielende Entwickelung blickt, zum Gliede einer geistgemäßen Weltanschauung zu machen. Einer Weltanschauung, die die Menschenwesenheit in ihrer Entfaltung aus den Tiefen des Weltalls erkennen will. Wie Bergson zu dem bei ihm glitzernden, aus Preuß' Darstellung aber so kraftvoll leuchtenden Gedanken gekommen ist: darauf soll in diesem Zusammenhange weniger Wert gelegt werden als vielmehr darauf, daß in den Schriften des wenig gekannten Preuß fruchtbarste Keime zu erblicken sind, die manchem eine stärkere Anregung geben könnten als die glitzernde Gestalt vermag, in der man sie bei Bergson wiederfindet. Allerdings muß man auch für Preuß mehr Anlage zur Gedankenvertiefung mitbringen, als sich bei denjenigen zeigte, die so viel Begeisterung für die Bergsonsche «Neubelebung» der Weltanschauung aufbrachten. Was hier gesagt worden ist, hat mit nationaler Zu- oder Abneigung gar nichts zu tun. In der letzten Zeit ist H. Bönke der «originellen philosophischen Neuschöpfung» Bergsons nachgegangen, weil dieser doch solch haßgetragene, verachtungsprühende Worte gegen das deutsche Geistesleben in dieser schicksaltragenden Zeit auszusprechen für nötig befunden hat. (Vergleiche die Schrift: Plagiator Bergson, Membre de l'Institut. Zur Antwort auf die Herabsetzung der deutschen Wissenschaft durch Edmond Perrier, Président de l'Academie des Sciences. Charlottenburg, Huth 1915.) In Anbetracht alles dessen, was Bönke nachweist über die Art, wie Bergson wiedergibt, was er dem deutschen Gedankenleben verdankt, ist wohl kaum übertrieben, was der Philosoph Wundt im Literarischen Centralblatt für Deutschland Nr.46 vom 13. November 1915 sagt: ... Bönke läßt es ... an belastendem Beweismaterial nicht fehlen. Seine Schrift besteht zum größten Teil aus Stellen, die den Werken Bergsons und Schopenhauers entnommen sind, und in denen der jüngere Autor die Gedanken des älteren entweder wörtlich oder mit geringer Variation wiederholt. Immerhin ist dies nicht allein entscheidend. Es wird darum zweckmäßig sein, die Beispiele, die Bönke ins Feld führt, einigermaßen nach kritischen Gesichtspunkten zu ordnen. Dann lassen sie sich wohl in drei Kategorien bringen. Eine erste enthält Sätze, die, abgesehen von unwesentlichen Unterschieden, bei beiden Schriftstellern genau übereinstimmen ...» In anderen Kategorien liegt die Übereinstimmung mehr in der Formung des Gedankens. Nun, es ist vielleicht wirklich weniger wichtig, inwieweit der deutsches Geistesleben so wütend verurteilende Bergson sich als ein recht williger Verarbeiter dieses deutschen Geisteslebens zeigt; wichtiger kann es aber scheinen, daß bei Bergson die Verarbeitung in leichtgewobenem, leicht erringbarem Nachdenken auftritt, und daß gar mancher Beurteiler besser getan hätte, mit der begeisterten Erhebung dieses «Neubelebers» der Weltanschauung zu warten, bis er durch besseres Verständnis derjenigen Denker, denen Bergson seine Anregungen verdankt, diese Erhebung - vielleicht unterlassen hätte. - Daß ein Nachfolger sich von seinen Vorgängern anregen läßt, ist eine übrigens naturgemäße Sache im Entwickelungsgange der Menschheit; es kommt aber darauf an, ob die Anregung zu einem Fortbildungsvorgang führt, oder - das geht auch aus Bönkes Darstellung klar hervor - wie bei Bergson zu einem Rückbildungsvorgang.

Ein Seitenblick

[ 16 ] Im Jahre 1912 ist erschienen «Das Hohe Ziel der Erkenntnis» von Omar al Raschid Bey (München, Verlag R. Piper). (Zu bemerken ist, daß der Verfasser kein Türke, sondern ein Deutscher ist, und daß die Ansicht, die er vertritt, nichts mit dem Mohammedanismus zu tun hat, sondern eine im modernen Gewande auftretende altindische Weltanschauung ist.) Das Buch ist nach dem Tode des Verfassers erschienen. Ein solches Buch würde in unserer Zeit nicht erscheinen, und sein Verfasser würde nicht glauben, sich und anderen mit dem darin Ausgesprochenen einen der Gegenwart entsprechenden Erkenntnisweg zeigen zu sollen, wenn er in seiner Seele die Bedingungen herstellen wollte, durch die ein Verständnis der Denkerreihe möglich ist, die in dieser Schrift geschildert wird. So wie für ihn die Dinge sich darstellen, könnte der Verfasser des «Hohen Zieles» für die hier ausgesprochene Behauptung nur ein mitleidiges Lächeln haben. Er würde nicht einsehen, daß alles, was er in seinem Schlußkapitel «Erwachen aus der Erscheinung» auf Grund des diesem Kapitel Vorangegangenen - und mit diesem - dem Seelenerleben darbietet, zwar ein rechter Erkenntnisweg war für das alte Indien, für den man als einen der Vergangenheit angehörigen volles Verständnis haben kann; daß aber dieser Erkenntnisweg in einen andern einmündet, wenn man nicht vorzeitig auf ihm stehen bleibt, sondern den geistgemäßen Wirklichkeitsweg wandelt, der von dem neueren Idealismus beschritten worden ist.

[ 17 ] Er hätte erkennen müssen, wie sein «Erwachen aus der Erscheinung» nur ein Schein des Erwachens ist; in Wirklichkeit ist es ein von dem eigenen seelischen Erleben bewirktes Sich-Zurückziehen von der Erscheinung - gleichsam ein Erbeben vor der Erscheinung - und dadurch nicht ein «Erwachen aus der Erscheinung», sondern ein Einschlafen im Wahn; ein Selbstwahn, der seine Wahnwelt für Wirklichkeit hält, weil er nicht dazu gelangt, den Weg in die geistgemäße Wirklichkeit zu gehen. Plancks sich selbstverleugnendes Denken ist ein Seelenerlebnis, zu dem al Raschids Wahndenken nicht dringen mag. Da findet man im «Hohen Ziel» die Sätze: «Wer sein Heil in dieser Welt sucht, der bleibt dieser Welt verfallen; dem ist kein Entrinnen aus ungestilltem Verlangen; dem ist kein Entrinnen aus nichtigem Spiel; dem ist kein Entrinnen aus den engen Fesseln des ‹Ich›. Wer sich aus dieser Welt nicht erhebt, der lebt und vergeht mit seiner Welt.» Vor diesen Sätzen stehen diese: «Wer sein Heil im ‹Ich› sucht, dem ist Selbstsucht Gebot, dem ist Selbstsucht Gottheit.» Wer aber die treibenden Seelenkräfte, die in Denkern der Reihe von Fichte bis Planck walten, lebensvoll erkennt, der durchschaut den Trug, der in diesen Sätzen des «Hohen Zieles» sich ausspricht. Denn er erkennt, wie die Sucht nach dem Selbst - die Selbstsucht - vor dem Erleben des «Ich» im Fichteschen Sinn liegt, und wie das Fliehen der Ich-Anerkennung - im altindischen Sinn - das hochmütige Erkenntuisstreben scheinbar weiter in die Geistwelt hineinführt, in Wirklichkeit aber zurückwirft in die Sucht nach dem Ich. Denn erst das Finden des Ich läßt das Ich entrinnen den Fesseln der Sucht nach dem Ich, der Selbstsucht. Es kommt eben durchaus darauf an, ob man im «Erwachen aus der Erscheinung» die vom Rückfall in die Ich-Sucht verursachten Erlebnisse des «Hohen Zieles» hat, oder ob man Erlebnisse hat, auf die folgende Worte deuten können. Wer sein Heil im Fliehen des «Ich» sucht, der verfällt der Sucht nach dem «Ich»; wer das «Ich» findet, befreit sich von der Sucht nach dem Ich; denn Sucht nach dem Ich schafft das Ich zu seinem eigenen Götzen; Finden des «Ich» gibt das Ich der Welt. Wer sein Heil im Fliehen der Welt sucht, der wird von der Welt in seinen eigenen Wahn zurückgeworfen; den täuscht hochmütiger Erkenntniswahn und läßt ihm nicht'ges Ideen-Spiel als Weltenwahrheit erscheinen; der löst von vorne die Fesseln des Ich und sieht nicht, wie der Feind der Erkenntnis sie von hinten ihm nur fester anlegt. Wer sich, die Weltoffenbarung verschmähend, über die Welt erheben will, der führt sich in den Wahn, der ihn um so sicherer hält, als er ihm sich als Weisheit offenbart. - In den Wahn, mit dem man sich und andere vor dem schwierigen Erwachen in dem neueren Weltanschauungs-Idealismus zurückhält, und in ein «Erwachen aus der Erscheinung» hineinträumt. Ein vermeintliches Erwachen, wie es das «Hohe Ziel» weisen will, ist zwar ein Quell zu jenem Erlebnis, das immer erneut dem «Erwachten» von der Erhabenheit seiner Erkenntnis sprechen läßt, aber auch ein Hindernis für das Erleben dieses Weltanschauungs-Idealismus. Man nehme diese Bemerkungen nicht so, als ob der Verfasser dieser Schrift das Erkenntnisstreben al Raschid Beys in seiner Art irgendwie herabsetzen wollte; was er hier sagt, ist nur der ihm notwendig erscheinende Einwand gegen eine Weltanschauung, die ihm in dem ärgsten Selbstwahn zu leben scheint. Solchen Einwand kann man wohl auch machen, wenn man eine geistige Erscheinung von einem gewissen Gesichtspunkte aus schätzt; vielleicht kann es einem gerade dann am notwendigsten erscheinen, weil der Ernst dazu zwingt, der in der Behandlung von Erkenntnisfragen walten muß.

A forgotten current in German thought

[ 1 ] Fichte, Schelling and Hegel appear in their full significance especially to those who look at the far-reaching stimuli they had for personalities who had far less intellectual vigor than themselves. Something drives and works in the souls of these free thinkers that could not be fully expressed in themselves. And what thus drives as a basic tone in the souls of these thinkers: it continues to have a living effect in their successors and brings them to spiritually appropriate world views that could not be achieved by the great predecessors themselves, because they had to exhaust their spiritual resilience in their first attempts, so to speak.

[ 2 ] So in Johann Gottlieb Fichte's son, Immanuel Hermann Fichte, a thinker emerges who attempts to penetrate the spiritual more deeply than his father, and than Schelling and Hegel. Whoever dares to make such an attempt will not only hear from the outside the contradiction of all those who are anxious about worldview issues apart from him; if he is a level-headed thinker, he will also clearly perceive this contradiction from within his own soul. Is there really a possibility of releasing powers of knowledge in the human soul that lead into areas from which the senses give no insight? What can guarantee the reality of such areas, what can characterize the difference between such reality and the products of fantasy and reverie? He who does not have the spirit of this contradiction always at his side, as it were, like the faithful companion of his prudence, will easily stumble with his attempts at spiritual science; he who has it will recognize in it a great value in life. - Whoever delves into Immanuel Hermann Fichte's explanations will find that he has inherited from his great predecessors a way of thinking that strengthens his steps into the spiritual realm just as much as it gives him prudence in the sense indicated.

[ 3 ] The point of view of Hegel's worldview, which makes the spiritual nature of the world of ideas the fundamental conviction, could also be the starting point for Immanuel Hermann Fichte's development of thought. But he felt it to be a weakness of this world view that from its supersensible point of view it only sees what is evident in the world of the senses. Anyone who follows Immanuel Hermann Fichte's views can experience the following as their keynotes. The soul experiences itself in a supersensible way when it rises above sensory perception to weave in the realm of ideas. It has thus not only enabled itself to view the sense world differently than the senses view it - which would correspond to Hegel's world view - but it has a self-experience that it cannot have through anything that can be found in the sense world. It now knows of something that is itself supersensible about it. This "something" cannot merely be "the idea" of its sensual body. Rather, it must be a living entity that underlies the sensory body in such a way that it is formed in the sense of its idea. Thus Immanuel Hermann Fichte is led beyond the sensual body to a supersensible body, which forms the former out of its life. Hegel progresses from sense perception to thinking about sense perception. Fichte seeks in man the being that can experience thinking as a supersensible one. Hegel, if he wants to see something supersensible in thinking, would have to ascribe to this thinking itself the ability to think. Fichte cannot go along with this. He must say to himself: If one is not to regard the sensory body itself as the producer of thought, then one is forced to assume a supersensible beyond it. Driven by such a view, Fichte considers the human sensory body from a scientific (physiological) point of view, and he finds that such a view, if it is only impartial enough, is compelled to assume a supersensible body as the basis of the sensory body. In the 118th and 119th paragraphs of his "Anthropology" (2nd edition 1860) he says: "In the material elements, therefore, the truly persistent, that unifying principle of form of the body cannot be found, which proves to be effective throughout our whole life". - "Thus we are pointed to a second, essentially different cause in the body." - "In that" this "contains what is actually persistent in the metabolism, it is the true, inner, invisible, but in all visible materiality present body. The other, the outer appearance of the same, formed from incessant metabolism, may henceforth be called 'body', which is truly not persistent and not one, the mere effect or afterimage of that inner corporeality which throws it into the changing world of matter, just as, for example, the magnetic force prepares an apparently dense body from the parts of iron filing dust, but which atomizes in all directions when the binding force is withdrawn from it." For Fichte, this opens up the prospect of escaping from the world of the senses, in which man operates between birth and death, into a supersensible world to which he is linked by the invisible body in the same way as he is linked to the sensible world by the visible body. For the realization of this invisible body leads him to the view that he expresses with the words: "For there is hardly any need to ask here how man behaves in himself - in this process of death? Even after the last act of the life process, which is invisible to us, he remains in his being completely the same according to spirit and organizational power as he was before. Its integrity is preserved; for it has lost absolutely nothing of what its was and belonged to its substance during visible life. He only returns to the invisible world in death, or rather, since he had never left it, since it is the actual persistence in everything visible, - he has only shed a certain form of visibility. 'Being dead' merely means no longer remaining perceptible (perceptible) to the ordinary conception of the senses, in quite the same way as the actually real, the ultimate causes of bodily phenomena are impereceptible (imperceptible) to the senses." And Fichte feels so secure in the supersensible world with such a thought that he can say: "With this concept of the continuation of the soul we therefore not only skip over experience and reach over into an unknown realm of merely illusory existences, but with it we find ourselves right in the middle of the comprehensible reality accessible to thought. The opposite of this, to assert a cessation of the soul, would be contrary to nature, contrary to all analogy of experience. The 'dead' soul, i.e. the soul that has become invisible to the senses, continues to exist no less, unaffected by its original conditions of life. ... Its organizing power must only be presented with a different means of embodiment in order to stand there in new bodily effectiveness...." (p 133 and p 134 of Fichte's "Anthropology".)

[ 4 ] From such views, the possibility of a self-knowledge of man opens up for Immanuel Hermann Fichte, which he attains when he looks at himself from the point of view which he gains through experiencing his supersensible being. His sensual being brings man to the point of thinking. But in thinking he grasps himself as a supersensible being. If he raises mere thinking to inner experience, whereby it is no longer mere thinking but supersensible contemplation, he gains a kind of knowledge through which he no longer merely looks at the sensible but at the supersensible. If anthropology is the science of man when he observes his part in the sensory world, then through the contemplation of the supersensible another science comes to light, about which Immanuel Hermann Fichte expresses himself thus (p 270): ". ... anthropology ends in the conclusion, founded from the most diverse sides, that man, according to the true quality of his being, as in the actual source of his consciousness, belongs to a supersensible world. Sense-consciousness, on the other hand, and the phenomenal world (world of appearances) which arises at its eye-points, with the whole, also human, sense-life, have no other meaning than to be only the place in which that supersensible life of the spirit takes place, by introducing the other-worldly spiritual content of ideas into the sense-world by free conscious action. ..." This thorough understanding of the human being now elevates "anthropology" in its final result to "anthroposophy".


[ 5 ] Through Immanuel Hermann Fichte, the cognitive drive that manifests itself in German worldview idealism was brought to take the first of those steps that can lead human insight to a science of the spiritual world. Just as Immanuel Hermann Fichte sought to carry forward the ideas of his predecessors: Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Schelling and Hegel, many other minds strove to do the same. For this German idealism points to the germinal force of a real development of those powers of human cognition which see the supersensible-spiritual in the same way as the senses see the sensible-material. Here we shall only look at a few of these spirits. Just how fruitful the German idealistic intellectual current proved to be in this direction can be seen if one looks not only at those spirits who are treated in the usual handbooks on the history of philosophy, but also at those whose intellectual activity was confined within narrower boundaries. There are, for example, "Kleine Schriften" by Johann Heinrich Deinhardt, who died on August 16, 1867 in Bromberg as a grammar school director (Hermann Schmidt published these writings in 1869 in Leipzig, with B.G. Teubner). It contains essays on "the contrast between pantheism and deism in the pre-Christian religions", on "the concept of religion", on "Kepler, life and character", etc. The basic tone of these essays is certainly one that shows how their author's thought life is rooted in German worldview idealism. One of the essays talks about the "rational reasons for the immortality of the human soul". This essay initially defends immortality only on the grounds that arise from ordinary thinking. Only at the end is the following significant note from the editor: "According to a letter to the editor dated August 14, 1866, the author intended to expand this essay in the complete edition of his collected short writings with a comment on the new body that the soul had already developed in this life. His death the following year prevented this plan from being carried out." How such a remark sheds light on the stimuli that drove the spirits from German worldview idealism to penetrate the spiritual realm in a scientific manner! How many such attempts would someone find at the present time if he were to pursue only those that are still to be found in the literature! How many can be assumed to have borne fruit not for literature, but for life! We are looking at a current of German intellectual life that has really been more or less forgotten in the prevailing scientific consciousness of the time.

[ 6 ] One of those spirits who is hardly spoken of today is Ignaz Paul Vitalis Troxler. Among his numerous writings, his "Lectures on Philosophy", published in 1835, are worth mentioning here. Through them, a personality expresses himself who is fully aware of how man, who uses only his senses and the intellect that calculates with the observations of the senses, can only recognize a part of the world. Like Immanuel Hermann Fichte, Troxler also feels that his thinking is situated in a supersensible world. But he also senses how man, when he is enraptured by the power that binds him to the senses, can not only place himself before a world that is thought in the Hegelian sense, but how through this enrapture he experiences in his inner being the blossoming of purely spiritual means of cognition, through which he sees a spiritual world spiritually, just as the senses see the sensory world sensually. Troxler speaks of a "super-spiritual sense". And we can form an idea of what he means by this in the following way. Man observes the things of the world through his senses. This gives them sensory images of things. They then think about these images. This gives rise to thoughts that no longer carry the sensory-imagery within them. Through the power of his mind, man thus adds supersensible thoughts to the sensory images. If he now experiences himself in the entity that thinks in him, so that he rises above mere thinking to spiritual experience, then an inner purely spiritual power of visualization takes hold of him from this experience. He then sees a world in images that can serve as a revelation of supersensibly experienced reality. These images are not received from the senses; but they are full of life like the sensory images; they are not the results of a reverie, but the experiences in the supersensible world captured in images by the soul. In ordinary cognition the sense-image is present first, and the thought is added in the process of cognition - the thought that is not sense-image-like. In the spiritual process of cognition the supersensible experience is present; this could not be seen as such if it did not pour itself through a power natural to the spirit into the image that brings it to spiritual-visual sensualization. For Trox1er, such cognition is that of the "super-spiritual sense". And the images of this super-spiritual sense are grasped by the "supersensible spirit" of man in the same way as the sensual images are grasped by reason in sensory cognition. According to Troxler's view, spirit cognition develops in the interaction of the supersensible spirit with the supersensible sense (compare the sixth of Troxler's "Lectures on Philosophy"). Starting from such premises, Troxler senses in the human being who experiences himself in the sensory world a "higher human being" who underlies this and who belongs to the supersensible world; and in this opinion he feels himself to be in agreement with what Friedrich Schlegel has expressed. And so, like Friedrich Schlegel before him, the highest qualities and activities of man that reveal themselves in the world of the senses become expressions of the abilities of the supersensible man. As man stands in the world of the senses, his soul is endowed with the power of faith. But this is only the revelation of the supersensible soul through the sensible body. In the supersensible, the power of faith is based on an ability of the soul which - if one wants to express it in a supersensible, figurative way - must be called an accessory of the supersensible human being. And so it is with the power of hope. It is based on a seeing of the supersensible human being; the activity in love corresponds in the "higher human being" to the ability to "feel" in the spirit, to touch, just as the sense of feeling in the sensual world is the ability to touch. Troxler speaks about this (on page 107 of his "Lectures on Philosophy", Bern 1835) in the following way: "Our immortal friend, Friedrich Schlegel" has highlighted the relationship between the senses and the spirit "very beautifully and truly". In his lectures on the philosophy of language and the word, he says: "If one wants to find the first beginnings of our higher knowledge in that alphabet of consciousness, which gives the individual elements to the individual syllables and whole words, after God himself forms the keystone of the highest consciousness, then the feeling of the spirit must be accepted as the living center of the entire consciousness, and as the point of union with the higher. ... These basic feelings of the eternal are very often referred to as faith, hope and love. ... If these three basic feelings, or qualities, or states of consciousness, are to be regarded as just as many organs of knowledge and perception, or if one prefers, at least organs of intuition of the divine, then in this respect, and in relation to the form of perception peculiar to each of them, they may well be compared to the external senses and sensory instruments. Love, then, in the first exciting touch of the soul, in the continual attraction, and finally perfect union, corresponds strikingly to the outer sense of feeling; faith is the inner hearing of the spirit, which unites, grasps and preserves within itself the given word of a higher communication; hope, however, is the eye whose light beholds the objects longed for with deep desire even from afar." The words that Troxler adds show that he goes beyond the meaning that Schlegel gives to these sentences and thinks of them in the sense indicated above: "Far above understanding and will, like their interaction, far above reason and freedom, and their unity, these ideas of mind uniting in a consciousness of mind and heart are sublime, and just as understanding and will, reason and freedom, and all the faculties and faculties of the soul lying beneath them represent a reflection turned earthward, these three are a consciousness directed heavenward, illuminated by a truly divine light. " The same is shown by the fact that Troxler also speaks about the supersensible soul body in the same way as Immanuel Hermann Fichte: "Even earlier, philosophers distinguished a fine, noble soul body from the coarser body ... a soul that had an image of the body in itself, which they called Schema, and which was to them the inner higher man.... In recent times, even Kant, in the dreams of a spirit seer, seriously jokingly dreams of a whole inner spiritual man who carries all the limbs of the outer one on his spiritual body; Lavater writes poetry and thinks in the same way; and even when Jean Paul jokes humorously about Bonet's undergarment and Platner's soul-laced body, which are supposed to be in the coarser body overcoat and torture gown, we also hear him ask again, 'for what purpose and from where were these extraordinary dispositions and desires placed in us, which merely slowly cut our earthy shell like swallowed diamonds? ... In the stony limbs (of man) his living ones grow and mature according to a way of life unknown to us'. We could" - Troxler continues - "cite a myriad of similar ways of thinking and poetry, which in the end are only different views and ideas in which ... the true, single doctrine of the individuality and immortality of man" is contained.

[ 7 ] Troxler also speaks of the possibility of a science of man on the path of knowledge he seeks, through which - to use his own terms - the "supersensible sense" in union with the "supersensible spirit" grasp the supersensible essence of man in an "anthroposophy". On 5.101 of his "Lectures" we find the sentence: "If it is now most gratifying that the latest philosophy, which ... in every anthroposophy ... ... is emerging, it cannot be overlooked that this idea cannot be a fruit of speculation, and that the true individuality of man must neither be confused with that which it posits as subjective spirit or finite ego, nor with that which it opposes to it as absolute spirit or absolute personality."

[ 8 ] There is no doubt that Troxler sought his way beyond Hegel's world of thought more in a dark feeling than in a clear view. Nevertheless, one can observe in his cognitive life how the stimuli of the German worldview idealism of Fichte, Schelling and Hegel have an effect on a personality who cannot make the views of this freedom of thought his own; but who finds his own way by receiving these stimuli.


[ 9 ] Karl Christian Planck is one of the forgotten personalities of German intellectual development who has gone unnoticed during his lifetime. He was born in Stuttgart in 1819 and died in 1880; he was a professor at the grammar school in Ulm and later at the seminary in Blaubeuren. As late as 1877, he hoped that he would be offered the then vacant chair of philosophy in Tübingen. It did not happen. In a series of writings, he sought to approach a world view that seemed to him to be the expression of the spiritual nature of the German people. In his book "Grundlinien einer Wissenschaft der Natur" (1864), he expresses how he wanted to represent the thoughts of the inquiring German people's soul with his own thoughts: "What power of deep-rooted prejudices from the previous view is opposed to his - the author's - writing, of which he is fully aware; However, just as the work itself, despite all the unfavorable circumstances that stood in the way of a work of this kind due to the author's entire situation and professional position, has nevertheless fought for its realization and its way into the public eye, so he is also certain that what is only now gaining its recognition, what now has to fight for its recognition will one day appear as the simplest and most self-evident truth, and that in it not only his cause, but the truly German view of things will triumph over all still unworthy external and un-German conceptions of nature and the spirit. - What our medieval poetry already foreshadowed in unconscious, profound foreboding will finally be fulfilled in our nation in the maturity of the times. The impractical inwardness of the German spirit, afflicted with harm and ridicule (as Wolfram describes it in his Parzival), will finally attain the highest in the power of its ceaseless striving; it will look to the bottom of the last simple laws of things and of human existence itself; and what poetry has symbolized in a fantastically medieval way in the wonders of the Grail, whose dominion its hero attains, will conversely receive its purely natural fulfilment and reality in the lasting knowledge of nature and the spirit itself." - In the last period of his life, Karl Christian Planck summarized his thoughts in a book published in 1881 by the philosopher Karl Köstlin as the "Testament of a German".

[ 10 ] It is quite possible to perceive a similar kind of perception of the puzzle of knowledge in Planck's soul as is revealed in the other thinkers characterized in this work. This cognitive puzzle in its original form becomes the starting point of Planck's research. Is the power to be found in the world of human thought through which man can grasp true reality, the reality that gives his existence meaning and significance in the world? Man sees himself in nature and confronts it. He can certainly think about what is at work in its depths as true essential forces; but where is the guarantee that his thoughts have any other meaning than that they are creatures of his own soul, without relationship to those depths? If they were, man would have to remain unaware of what he himself is and how he is rooted in the true world. To want to approach the depths of the world through any other power of the soul than through thinking was as far from Planck's mind as it was from Hegel's. He could have no other view than that true reality must somehow surrender itself to thinking. But no matter how far one reaches out with thinking, no matter how one tries to strengthen its inner power, one always remains in thinking; one does not encounter being in the vastness and depths of thinking. Through its own essence, thinking seems to exclude itself from any communion with being. But for Planck, the insight into this alienation of thinking from being is precisely the ray of light that shines on the riddle of the world. If thinking does not claim to somehow carry something of reality in itself, if it truthfully reveals itself as the unreal, then it proves to be the very tool to express reality. If it were itself a real thing, then the soul could only weave in its reality and would not come out of it; if it is itself unreal, then it does not disturb the soul through its own reality; man, in thinking, is not at all in a thought-reality, but in the thought-unreality, which for this very reason does not impose itself on man with its own reality, but expresses the reality of which it speaks. Whoever sees something real in thought itself must, in Planck's view, renounce any approach to reality; for him, thought must place itself between the soul and reality. If thinking itself is nothing, i.e. if it cannot conceal reality from cognition, then reality must be able to reveal itself in thinking.

[ 11 ] With this view, Planck initially only gained the starting point for his world view. For in the web of thoughts that the soul has directly in life, pure, self-denying, even negating thinking is by no means effective. What lives in the imagining, feeling, willing and desiring of the soul plays into this. Because this is so, the clouding of the world view arises. And Planck's endeavor is to attain such a worldview in which everything it contains is the result of thinking, but nothing originates from thinking itself. In everything that is made into a thought about the real world, we must look at what lives in thought without itself being conceived. Planck paints his world view with a thinking that gives itself up in order to let the world shine out of itself.

[ 12 ] As an example of how Planck wants to arrive at a world view in such a striving, let us mark with a few strokes how he thinks about the nature of the earth. - If someone imagines the earth in the way that purely physical geology entails, then there is no truth in this idea for Planck's world view. To imagine the earth in this way would be like speaking of a tree and only considering the trunk without leaves, flowers and fruit. Such a trunk can be called reality to the physical eye. In a higher sense, it is not reality. For it cannot exist in the context of the world as it is. It can only be what it is because the driving forces that develop leaves, blossoms and fruit arise in it at the same time. In the reality of the trunk we must also think of these driving forces and must be aware that the mere trunk only gives a picture of reality that is deceptive about itself. The fact that something is there before the senses is no proof that it is also a reality. Imagining the earth as the totality of what it shows in terms of mineral formations and facts occurring within these formations is not a reality. Whoever wants to imagine something real about the earth must imagine it in such a way that its mineral kingdom already contains within itself the plant kingdom, just as the trunk structure of the tree contains the leaves and blossoms; indeed, that the animal kingdom and man are already included in the "true earth". One does not say that this is a matter of course, and that Planck is basically only deceiving himself by saying that everyone thinks this as he does. Planck would have to reply: where is he who does this? Certainly, everyone presents the earth as the body of the world with its plants, animals and people. But they present the mineral earth, consisting of its geological layers, with plants growing out of its surface and animals and human beings walking around on it. But this sum earth, made up of minerals, plants, animals and humans, does not exist. It is merely an illusion of the senses. Instead there is a true earth, which is a completely supersensible entity, an invisible being, which gives itself the mineral subsoil out of itself; but does not exhaust itself in this, but continues to reveal itself in the plant kingdom, then in the animal kingdom, then in the human kingdom. For the mineral kingdom, the plant kingdom, the animal kingdom, the human kingdom, only he has the right view who sees the whole of the earth in its supersensuousness, and who feels how, for example, the idea of the material mineral kingdom in itself, without the idea of the development of the soul of mankind, is a delusion. Certainly, one can imagine a material mineral kingdom; but one lives in the lie of the world and not in the truth of the world if one does not have the feeling that with such an idea one is under the same delusion as if one wanted to think that a man whose head has been cut off will continue to walk calmly through life: If true knowledge necessitated what is indicated here, then it could never be attained; for he who claims that the mineral earth is not a reality because it must be seen in the whole of the earth should also say that the whole of the earth must be seen again in the plant system and so on. Whoever makes such an objection has not grasped the meaning of what underlies a spiritual world view. The point of all cognition is not merely that one thinks correctly, but that one also thinks in accordance with reality. Whoever speaks of a painting can certainly say that one does not think realistically if one only looks at one person while there are three in the painting; but this assertion within its scope cannot be refuted by saying that no one understands this painting who does not also know all the previous ones by the same painter. To recognize reality, correct and realistic thinking is necessary. To regard the mineral as a mineral, the plant as a plant, and so on, can be in accordance with reality; the mineral earth is not a real, but a figment of the imagination; even if one is aware that it is only a part of everything earthly.-This is the significant thing about such a personality as Planck, that he brings himself into a mood through which he does not conceive the truth of a thought, but experiences it. That it develops a power for itself in its own soul, through which it experiences when a thought may not be thought, because it kills itself through its own essence. To grasp the existence of a reality that carries its own life and death within itself belongs to such a state of soul that does not rely on the sensory world to tell it: this is, or this is not.

[ 13 ] From this point of view, Planck sought to understand what lives in natural phenomena, in human existence, in historical, artistic and legal life. He wrote about the "truth and shallowness of Darwinism" in an ingenious book. He called this work a "landmark in the history of modern (1872) German science". There are people who have the feeling that a personality like Planck hovers in unworldly conceptual heights and has no sense of practical life. This requires people who form their sound judgment based on "real" life, as it is called. Now, one can also have the opinion that many things would be different in real life if this ponderous view of life and the practice of life were less widespread in reality. If, on the other hand, the opinion could become somewhat more widespread that thinkers like Planck, because they acquire a constitution of soul through which they connect themselves with true reality, also have a truer judgment of the conditions of life than those who call them conceptualists and impractical philosophers. The opinion is also possible that the dullards, who are averse to such alleged "conceptual giddiness" and think themselves to be quite practical in life, lose the scent for the true conditions of life, while the impractical philosophers use it precisely for accuracy. One can arrive at such an opinion if one looks at Planck and sees in him a far-sighted, accurate judgment for the needs of real life practice and for the events of external life combined with the height of philosophical idea formation. Even if one disagrees with Planck about some of the ideas he developed about the external organization of life - which is also true of the author of this book - one can nevertheless concede that his views can provide a viable starting point for practical questions in this area in particular, from which one can proceed; even if the progression leads to something quite different from what is assumed. And one would think that people who are "conceptual enthusiasts" of this kind and thus see through the forces at work in real life are better suited to the needs of this real life than some who believe themselves to be saturated with practical life precisely because, in their view, they have not allowed themselves to be "made stupid" by contact with any world of ideas. -(The author of this essay spoke about Karl Christian Planck's position in the development of worldviews in recent times in his book "Welt- und Lebensanschauungen im neunzehnten Jahrhundert", published in 1900, which appeared in a new edition in 1914 under the title "Die Rätsel der Philosophie"). Someone might think that it is unjustified to regard Planck's thoughts as significant for the driving forces of the German people, since these thoughts have found little dissemination. Such an opinion fails to recognize what is important when we speak of the effect of the people's essence in the views of a people's thinkers. What is at work there are the impersonal (often subconscious) forces of the people, which live in the activities of the people in the most varied areas of existence and which also shape the ideas in such a thinker. These forces were there before his appearance, are active after it; they live even when they are not spoken of; they also live when they are misjudged. And it may be that they work in a particularly strong way in such a popular thinker who is not spoken of, because until the opinions formed about him are formed, what such powers harbor radiates less than into his thoughts. Such a thinker can often stand alone, not only during his life, and his thoughts can also stand alone in the opinions of posterity. But if one has grasped the character of his thoughts, then one has recognized a trait of the national soul, a trait that has become a thought in him and that remains indestructible in the nation, ready to reveal itself in ever new impulses. Regardless of the question: what was granted to him to work, the other question is: what worked in him? And what will always lead to similar achievements? The second edition of Karl Christian Planck's "Testament of a German" was published in 1912. It is a pity that many a philosopher's mind with a penchant for writing was more enthusiastic at the time about Henri Bergson's lightly woven worldview ideas, which were therefore easier for undemanding souls to understand, than about Planck's strictly structured, far-reaching ideas. What has been written about Bergson's "reshaping" of the worldview, especially by those who discover the novelty of a worldview so easily because they lack the understanding, sometimes even the knowledge, of what has long been there. With regard to the "novelty" of one of Bergson's main ideas, the author of this essay has also pointed out the following important fact in his book "Rätsel der Philosophie". (It should be noted in passing that this reference was written before the present war. Compare the preface to the second volume of the aforementioned book.)-Bergson's thoughts lead to a transformation of the widespread idea of the development of organic beings. He does not place the simplest living being at the beginning of this development, in order then to think of the more complicated beings up to man emerging from it through external forces, but he imagines that at the starting point of development there is a being that already contains in some form the impulse to become man. But it can only bring this drive to realization by first separating from itself other drives that also lie within it. In the separation of the lower life beings it gains the power to realize the higher ones. Thus the human being is, according to his nature, not the last thing to come into being, but the first thing to take effect before everything else. He first separates the other beings from his formative powers in order to gain the strength for his emergence into external sensual reality through this preliminary work. Of course, some will object: well, many have already thought that an inner developmental instinct is at work in the development of living beings. And it will be possible to cite the long-standing idea of purposefulness, or views held by natural scientists such as Nägeli and others. However, in a case such as the one in question here, such objections do not hit the mark. For Bergson's thought is not concerned with starting from a general idea of an inner power of development, but from a definite conception of what man is in his full extent; and to see from this conception that this supersensibly conceived man has in himself the impulses to place the other beings of nature first in sensuous reality and then also to place himself in it.

[ 14 ] Now we have the following. What can be read in Bergson's dazzling, lightly abbreviated development of ideas has before been expressed in a thoughtful, powerful way by the German thinker Wilhelm Heinrich Preuß. Preuß is now also one of those personalities who belong to the more or less forgotten current of a spiritually appropriate German worldview development described here. With a powerful sense of reality, Preuß combines nature and world view - for example in his book "Geist und Stoff" (1882). The Bergsonian thought mentioned above is expressed by him as follows: "It may be ... be time to develop a ... theory of the origin of organic species, which is not based solely on one-sided propositions from descriptive natural science, but is also in full agreement with the other laws of nature, which are also the laws of human thought. A doctrine at the same time that is devoid of all hypothesizing and is based only on strict conclusions from scientific observations in the broadest sense; a doctrine that rescues the concept of species according to actual possibility, but at the same time takes over the concept of development established by Darwin into its field and seeks to make it fruitful. -The center of this new doctrine is now man, the only once on our planet recurring species: Homo sapiens. It is curious that the older observers began with the objects of nature and then lost their way to such an extent that they could not find their way to man, which even Darwin only succeeded in doing in the most miserable and thoroughly unsatisfactory way by searching for the progenitor of the Lord of Creation among the animals - while the natural scientist would have to begin with himself as man in order to return progressively through the whole field of being and thinking to mankind ... It was not by chance that human nature emerged from earthly nature, but by necessity. Man is the goal of the telluric processes, and every other form emerging alongside him has borrowed its features from his own. Man is the first-born being of the whole cosmos ... When his germs had emerged, the remaining organic residue no longer had the necessary strength to produce further human germs. What remained became animal or plant ..."

[ 15 ] The idea of the essence of man as it lives in the philosophy of German idealism also shines through in these ideas of the little-known thinker from Elsfleth, Wilhelm Heinrich Preuß. With this view, he knows how to make Darwinism, insofar as it only looks at the development that takes place in the sensory world, a part of a spiritual world view. A world view that wants to recognize the human being in its unfolding from the depths of the universe. How Bergson arrived at his glittering thought, which shines so powerfully from Preuß' presentation, is less important in this context than the fact that in the writings of the little-known Preuß one can see the most fruitful seeds, which could give many a stronger stimulus than the glittering form in which one finds them in Bergson. However, for Preuß, too, one must have a greater aptitude for deepening thought than was evident in those who showed so much enthusiasm for Bergson's "revitalization" of the world view. What has been said here has nothing at all to do with national liking or disliking. In recent times, H. Bönke has investigated Bergson's "original philosophical neologism", because he found it necessary to utter such hateful, contemptuous words against German intellectual life in these fateful times. (Compare the writing: Plagiator Bergson, Membre de l'Institut. In response to the disparagement of German science by Edmond Perrier, President of the Academie des Sciences. Charlottenburg, Huth 1915) In view of all that Bönke proves about the way Bergson reproduces what he owes to German thought, it is hardly an exaggeration what the philosopher Wundt says in Literarisches Centralblatt für Deutschland No. 46 of November 13, 1915: ... Bönke leaves it ... is not lacking in incriminating evidence. His writing consists for the most part of passages taken from the works of Bergson and Schopenhauer, in which the younger author repeats the thoughts of the older either verbatim or with slight variation. Nevertheless, this is not the only decisive factor. It will therefore be expedient to organize the examples that Bönke brings into the field to some extent according to critical aspects. They can then be divided into three categories. The first contains sentences which, apart from insignificant differences, are exactly the same in both writers ..." In other categories, the agreement lies more in the shaping of the thought. Now, it is perhaps really less important to what extent Bergson, who so furiously condemns German intellectual life, shows himself to be a quite willing processor of this German intellectual life; but it may seem more important that with Bergson the processing occurs in easily woven, easily attainable reflection, and that many an evaluator would have done better to wait with the enthusiastic elevation of this "reviver" of the world view until, through better understanding of those thinkers to whom Bergson owes his inspiration, he might have refrained from this elevation. - The fact that a successor allows himself to be inspired by his predecessors is, incidentally, a natural part of the development of humanity; what matters, however, is whether the inspiration leads to a process of further development or - as is also clear from Bönke's account - to a process of regression, as in Bergson's case.

A sideways glance

[ 16 ] In 1912, "Das Hohe Ziel der Erkenntnis" by Omar al Raschid Bey was published (Munich, Verlag R. Piper). (It should be noted that the author is not a Turk, but a German, and that the view he represents has nothing to do with Mohammedanism, but is an ancient Indian world view in a modern guise). The book was published after the author's death. Such a book would not appear in our time, and its author would not believe that he was showing himself and others a path of knowledge corresponding to the present with what is expressed in it, if he wanted to create the conditions in his soul through which an understanding of the series of thinkers described in this writing is possible. The way things are for him, the author of the "High Aim" could only smile pityingly at the assertion made here. He would not realize that everything he presents in his concluding chapter "Awakening from Appearance" on the basis of the preceding chapter - and with it - was indeed a right path of knowledge for ancient India, for which one can have full understanding as one belonging to the past; but that this path of knowledge leads into another, if one does not stop prematurely on it, but walks the spiritual path of reality, which has been taken by the newer idealism.

[ 17 ] He should have recognized how his "awakening from appearance" is only a semblance of awakening; In reality, it is a withdrawal from the appearance caused by his own mental experience - an earthquake before the appearance, as it were - and thus not an "awakening from the appearance", but a falling asleep in delusion; a self-delusion that takes its delusional world for reality, because it does not manage to take the path into the spiritually appropriate reality. Planck's self-denying thinking is an experience of the soul that al Raschid's delusional thinking cannot reach. In the "High Goal" we find the sentences: "He who seeks his salvation in this world remains a slave to this world; he has no escape from unfulfilled desire; he has no escape from futile play; he has no escape from the narrow shackles of the 'I'. He who does not rise from this world lives and perishes with his world." These sentences are preceded by the following: "He who seeks his salvation in the 'I', to him selfishness is a commandment, to him selfishness is divinity." However, anyone who fully recognizes the driving forces of the soul, which rule in thinkers from Fichte to Planck, will see through the deception expressed in these sentences of the "High Goal". For he recognizes how the addiction to the self - the selfishness - lies before the experience of the "I" in the Fichtean sense, and how the fleeing of the recognition of the ego - in the old Indian sense - leads the haughty recognition of the ego apparently further into the spiritual world, but in reality throws it back into the addiction to the ego. For only the finding of the ego allows the ego to escape the shackles of the addiction to the ego, of selfishness. It depends on whether in the "awakening from the appearance" one has the experiences of the "high goal" caused by the relapse into ego addiction, or whether one has experiences to which the following words can point. He who seeks his salvation in fleeing the "I" falls into the addiction to the "I"; he who finds the "I" frees himself from the addiction to the I; for addiction to the I creates the I into its own idol; finding the "I" gives the I to the world. He who seeks his salvation by fleeing from the world is thrown back by the world into his own delusion; he is deceived by arrogant delusions of knowledge and allows his play of ideas to appear as the truth of the world; he loosens the fetters of the ego from the front and does not see how the enemy of knowledge only tightens them from behind. He who, spurning the revelation of the world, wants to rise above the world, leads himself into the delusion that holds him all the more securely as it reveals itself to him as wisdom. - Into the delusion with which one holds oneself and others back from the difficult awakening in the newer worldview idealism, and dreams oneself into an "awakening from appearance". A supposed awakening, as the "High Goal" wants to point out, is indeed a source for the experience that allows the "awakened" to speak again and again of the sublimity of his knowledge, but it is also an obstacle to experiencing this worldview idealism. One should not take these remarks as if the author of this writing wanted to somehow belittle al Raschid Bey's striving for knowledge in his own way; what he says here is only the objection that seems necessary to him against a worldview that seems to him to live in the worst self-delusion. Such an objection can certainly also be made if one appreciates a spiritual phenomenon from a certain point of view; perhaps it can seem most necessary to one precisely then, because the seriousness that must prevail in the treatment of questions of knowledge compels one to do so.